22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Some A is B (1)<br />

Every A is B (3)<br />

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 463<br />

is <strong>the</strong> contradictory <strong>of</strong><br />

is <strong>the</strong> contradictory <strong>of</strong><br />

No A is B (2)<br />

Some A is not B (4)<br />

(contradiction 1)<br />

(contradiction 2)<br />

‘Some A is B’ (1) should be equivalent to ‘Not: No A is B’(2 ′ ) (<strong>the</strong> contradictory<br />

<strong>of</strong> (2)) and ‘Every A is B’ (3) should be equivalent to ‘Not: Some A is not B’ (4 ′ )<br />

(<strong>the</strong> contradictory <strong>of</strong> (4)). If <strong>the</strong>se equivalences hold, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

terms in (1) and (2 ′ ) should be <strong>the</strong> same: A and B have determinate supposition<br />

in (1), so <strong>the</strong>y should have <strong>the</strong> same kind <strong>of</strong> supposition in (2 ′ ).<br />

For this to happen, <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation in (2 ′ ) should be to turn <strong>the</strong><br />

confused and distributive supposition <strong>of</strong> A and B in ‘No A is B’ into determinate<br />

supposition. This is indeed <strong>the</strong> rule proposed by Ockham: Never<strong>the</strong>less, it should<br />

be noted that <strong>the</strong> aforementioned rules hold only in <strong>the</strong> case where <strong>the</strong> term in<br />

question would not stand confusedly and distributively if <strong>the</strong> negation sign or <strong>the</strong><br />

relevant verb or name were taken away. For if <strong>the</strong> term were to stand confusedly<br />

and distributively when one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se expressions [negation sign] were taken<br />

away, <strong>the</strong>n with <strong>the</strong> addition <strong>of</strong> such an expression it would stand determinately.<br />

[Ockham, 1998, 214]<br />

Ockham’s rule can be formulated as follows:<br />

Rule 3o Dist(A)P &〈∼,A〉P∗ → Det(A)P ∗<br />

But what about <strong>the</strong> equivalence between (3) and (4 ′ )? In (3) A has confused<br />

and distributive supposition and B has merely confused supposition. So <strong>the</strong> same<br />

should occur in (4 ′ ). However, in ‘Some A is not B’, A has determinate supposition<br />

and B has confused and distributive supposition. According to rule 1, <strong>the</strong> negation<br />

would make A have confused and distributive supposition in (4 ′ ), that is, <strong>the</strong> same<br />

supposition <strong>of</strong> A in (3) (so far, so good). But what about B? According to <strong>the</strong> rule<br />

proposed by Ockham, since it has confused and distributive supposition in ‘Some<br />

A is not B’, it would have determinate supposition in (4 ′ ), under <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> negation. But in fact it ought to have merely confused supposition, because<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> equivalence between (3) and (4 ′ ). So <strong>the</strong> rule stated by Ockham does not<br />

safeguard this equivalence.<br />

Buridan, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, presents a rule that does safeguard <strong>the</strong> equivalence<br />

between (3) and (4 ′ ): A common term is confused nondistributively by two distributive<br />

[parts <strong>of</strong> speech] preceding it, ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> which would distribute it without<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. [Buridan, 2001, 275]<br />

Buridan’s rule can be formulated as follows:<br />

Rule 3b Dist(A)P &〈∼,A〉P∗ → Conf(A)P ∗<br />

That is, under <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> two negations, B in (4 ′ ) would have merely confused<br />

supposition, which is <strong>the</strong> desired result. But <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> equivalence between (1) and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!