22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

130 Ian Wilks<br />

(extensionally) “equal definition” [Abelard, p. 333 (21)]. But this definition has<br />

such equality with <strong>the</strong> thing defined only as a matter <strong>of</strong> fact (secundum actum rei),<br />

not according to nature (secundum naturam), since although no o<strong>the</strong>r rational<br />

and mortal animals are actually to be found except men, “nature does not seem<br />

to require this” [Abelard, p. 333 (32–33)]. In short, <strong>the</strong> above conditional (“If<br />

Socrates is a rational, mortal animal <strong>the</strong>n he is a man”) lacks <strong>the</strong> timeless necessity<br />

needed in order for a conditional to be true. This failing is based on <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

<strong>the</strong> requisite containment relation between consequent and antecedent does not<br />

exist; in particular, <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> “rational, mortal animal” does not contain<br />

<strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> “man.” So <strong>the</strong> above definitional principle fails to have a place in<br />

topical <strong>the</strong>ory as a maximal proposition. By parity <strong>of</strong> reasoning so do a number<br />

<strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs: “From whatever <strong>the</strong> definition is removed, so is <strong>the</strong> thing defined”;<br />

“Whatever is predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition is also predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing defined”<br />

and “Whatever is removed from <strong>the</strong> definition is removed from <strong>the</strong> thing defined”<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 331 (23-29)]. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing defined<br />

will be inclusive <strong>of</strong> whatever properties are appealed to in its definition; so if we<br />

take <strong>the</strong> first <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> above would-be maximal propositions and put “definition”<br />

for “thing defined,” and vice versa, we will acquire a perfectly good maximal<br />

proposition: “Whatever <strong>the</strong> thing defined is predicated <strong>of</strong>, so is <strong>the</strong> definition”<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 338 (4–5)]. 91<br />

Abelard works through a traditional list <strong>of</strong> maximal propositions and in similar<br />

fashion drops many entries from <strong>the</strong> list, making decisions in this regard which<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten at <strong>the</strong> outset non-obvious, even counter-intuitive. I append a few additional<br />

examples, which must suffice to indicate <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> this very extensive<br />

undertaking. (i) Under <strong>the</strong> topic “from genus,” Abelard accepts “Whatever <strong>the</strong><br />

genus is removed from so is <strong>the</strong> species” and “Whatever does not agree with <strong>the</strong><br />

genus does not agree with <strong>the</strong> species.” He rejects “Whatever is predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

genus in content (de contento) is also predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> species” and “Whatever<br />

<strong>the</strong> genus taken universally is predicated <strong>of</strong>, any <strong>of</strong> its species is predicated <strong>of</strong>”<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 340 (5–19)]. 92 (ii) Under <strong>the</strong> topic “from an integral whole”<br />

Abelard rejects inferences from whole to part. The maximal proposition “When<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole exists it is necessary that any part <strong>of</strong> it exist” endorses as true <strong>the</strong><br />

conditional “If <strong>the</strong>re is a house <strong>the</strong>re is a wall” [Abelard, 1970, p. 343 (34–36)].<br />

But this conditional is false. It is granted that <strong>the</strong> house as a whole cannot exist<br />

without ro<strong>of</strong>, wall and foundation. But saying that <strong>the</strong> house as a whole exists<br />

is simply not <strong>the</strong> same as saying that any one <strong>of</strong> those three components exists.<br />

The existence claims for <strong>the</strong> components are not part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence<br />

claim for <strong>the</strong> whole — which means that “If <strong>the</strong>re is a house <strong>the</strong>re is a<br />

91 The topic “from substance” is discussed in [Martin, 2004a, pp. 186–188].<br />

92 The reasoning behind <strong>the</strong>se results is given in [Stump, 1989, pp. 98–100]. The first (accepted)<br />

maximal proposition is exemplified with this true conditional: “If this rock is not an animal it<br />

is not a man” [Abelard, 1970, p. 340 (11)]. The second (accepted) maximal proposition is<br />

exemplified thus: “If no animal is a stone, no man is a stone” [Abelard, p. 340 (12)]. For <strong>the</strong><br />

idea <strong>of</strong> predicating a genus de contento, see de Rijk’s comment in [Abelard, 1970, p. lxxxiv, note<br />

3].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!