22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

192 Terence Parsons<br />

this is what Ockham intended (or should have intended). It is not clear, however,<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r a written or spoken connotative term directly signifies <strong>the</strong> same (complex)<br />

concept as does its nominal definition. Nor is it clear that all connotative terms can<br />

be ultimately eliminated from all nominal definitions. Ockham himself suggests<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rwise at SL III.26. 39<br />

It is an additional question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re are simple connotative terms in mental<br />

language. If so, <strong>the</strong>y have nominal definitions in mental language which are<br />

complex terms. The simple connotative terms must not be synonymous with<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir nominal definitions, because <strong>the</strong>n distinct terms in mental language would<br />

be synonyms, which Ockham rules out. So terms with nominal definitions are not<br />

synonymous with <strong>the</strong>ir definitions. Commentators disagree about whe<strong>the</strong>r this is<br />

<strong>the</strong> right thing to say about Ockham’s view.<br />

4 TYPES OF SUPPOSITION<br />

4.1 Univocation as <strong>the</strong> Source <strong>of</strong> Types <strong>of</strong> Supposition<br />

Aristotle uses ‘equivocation’ for a case in which things are called by <strong>the</strong> same name<br />

but <strong>the</strong> name does not have <strong>the</strong> same definition in each case. An example is ‘dog’,<br />

which can apply to one thing because it is a canine, and to ano<strong>the</strong>r because it is a<br />

certain star. So if you have inferred that something is a dog, and is not a dog, you<br />

haven’t inferred contradictory propositions40 unless ‘dog’ has <strong>the</strong> same definition<br />

in each proposition.<br />

According to Boethius, 41 <strong>the</strong>re is a similar way in which apparently contradictory<br />

propositions are not actually contradictory, even when you use <strong>the</strong> same word<br />

with <strong>the</strong> same definition in each application. His illustration is:<br />

[A] man walks homo ambulat<br />

Man does not walk homo non ambulat<br />

(Recall that <strong>the</strong>re are no articles in Latin, so <strong>the</strong> displayed Latin propositions<br />

are explicitly contradictory in form.) These propositions are not contradictory if<br />

‘homo’ in <strong>the</strong> first proposition stands for an individual man, and in <strong>the</strong> second<br />

proposition refers to <strong>the</strong> species man. This is not equivocation, because <strong>the</strong> word<br />

‘homo’ does not have different definitions in <strong>the</strong> two propositions. Boethius calls<br />

this phenomenon “univocation”. 42 Some medieval treatises were written explicitly<br />

about univocation.<br />

39See [Panaccio, 2004 4.2 (68-69)] for discussion <strong>of</strong> this point.<br />

40Equivocation is discussed along with o<strong>the</strong>r fallacies in Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations. A<br />

“refutation” is achieved when <strong>the</strong> respondent admits a proposition that contradicts <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

being defended. So <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> contradictoriness is central to that essay.<br />

41Boethius’s commentary on Aristotle’s On Interpretation, cited in De Rijk LM II.I.XV.1<br />

(492).<br />

42In essence <strong>the</strong> proposal is that univocation occurs when a word is used twice with <strong>the</strong> same<br />

signification, but what it stands for (its “supposition” or its “appellation”) changes. This kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> explanation is given e.g. in <strong>the</strong> Treatise on Univocation: “Univocation <strong>the</strong>refore is when <strong>the</strong><br />

appellation <strong>of</strong> a name varies and <strong>the</strong> signification remains <strong>the</strong> same.” (Second paragraph <strong>of</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!