22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

6 John Marenbon<br />

excusing himself for not going fur<strong>the</strong>r into <strong>the</strong> distinguishing features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first<br />

Category, substance, he comments that ‘since <strong>the</strong>y are clear in Aristotle himself,<br />

it seems superfluous to explain <strong>the</strong>m, especially since this discourse does not aim<br />

to put down everything that <strong>the</strong> Philosopher said, but to recount in a simpler way<br />

what seem obscure to <strong>the</strong> untrained.’ In practice, this means that <strong>the</strong> paraphraser<br />

omits some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> more complex ideas and concentrates on providing an elegant,<br />

lucid exposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Categories. On <strong>the</strong> question that had exercised readers <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> text since interest in it revived in <strong>the</strong> first century BC, whe<strong>the</strong>r it is about<br />

words or things, <strong>the</strong> paraphraser manages to maintain a neutral position. Aristotle<br />

begins — he says, following Themistius (Aristotle, 1961, 137:20 -138:1) — from<br />

<strong>the</strong> things that are perceived, but in order to discuss <strong>the</strong>m he has to talk about<br />

both <strong>the</strong> things that exist, and <strong>the</strong> things that are said, because what we perceive<br />

is produced by what exists and cannot be demonstrated except with <strong>the</strong> aid <strong>of</strong><br />

what is said. What will follow must <strong>the</strong>refore be a ‘mixed disputation’.<br />

Martianus Capella (E.L. Burge in [Stahl, 1971, 104-21], very unsatisfactory)<br />

Martianus Capella was a pagan, living in Roman North Africa ei<strong>the</strong>r near <strong>the</strong><br />

beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fifth century or c. 470 [Shanzer, 1986]. His one work is an<br />

encyclopaedia, in prose interspersed with verse passages, called On <strong>the</strong> Marriage<br />

<strong>of</strong> Mercury and Philology (De nuptiis Mercurii et Philologiae), because Books I<br />

and II tell <strong>the</strong> story <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> marriage <strong>of</strong> Mercury (divine reason) and Philology (<strong>the</strong><br />

human soul), an allegory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ascent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul to wisdom; Books III — IX<br />

[Martianus Capella, 1983] each treat one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Liberal Arts. Book IV is devoted<br />

to logic, and Book V to rhetoric. Both books need mentioning, because in Book IV<br />

Martianus treats <strong>the</strong> material <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Isagoge, <strong>the</strong>Categories and On Interpretation,<br />

followed by a presentation <strong>of</strong> syllogistic based on Apuleius (cf. [Sullivan, 1967, 170-<br />

3]) and, near <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book, an account <strong>of</strong> what he calls <strong>the</strong> ‘conditional<br />

syllogism’, in which he presents a list <strong>of</strong> seven modes that are <strong>the</strong> same as Cicero’s,<br />

but he is unusual in, at one point, giving <strong>the</strong>se seven modes in <strong>the</strong> traditional Stoic<br />

form, using numbers to stand for propositions (‘If <strong>the</strong> first, <strong>the</strong> second; <strong>the</strong> first;<br />

so <strong>the</strong> second’) [Martianus, 1983, 144]. Then, in Book V, Martianus goes into a<br />

presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics, based on Marius Victorinus. It has been argued that<br />

Victorinus originally incorporated Apuleius’s Peri hermeneias into his own work,<br />

and so Martianus is putting forward a thoroughly Victorine scheme <strong>of</strong> logic [Hadot,<br />

1971, 196].<br />

2.2 Boethius<br />

([Chadwick, 1981, 108-73; Marenbon, 2003, 17-65; Cameron, Forthcoming; Ebbesen,<br />

Forthcoming; Martin, Forthcoming])<br />

Boethius is <strong>the</strong> central figure in <strong>the</strong> ancient Latin tradition <strong>of</strong> logic. A small<br />

part <strong>of</strong> his importance is due to his continuing <strong>the</strong> tradition <strong>of</strong> Cicero and Marius<br />

Victorinus; <strong>the</strong> far larger part to his making — as a translator, a commentator<br />

and a writer <strong>of</strong> textbooks — Greek Aristotelian logic available to <strong>the</strong> Latin world

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!