22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 459<br />

concepts, just as much as spoken words, have different temporal occurrences: <strong>the</strong><br />

concept man does not correspond to one single concept that perdures in <strong>the</strong> intellect,<br />

but ra<strong>the</strong>r to each and every occurrence <strong>of</strong> this concept in <strong>the</strong> intellect every<br />

time it conceives <strong>of</strong> men, just as much as <strong>the</strong> spoken word ‘man’ corresponds to<br />

each <strong>of</strong> its temporal occurrences.<br />

Hence, if both simple supposition and material supposition concern a wide range<br />

<strong>of</strong> objects for which a term can supposit (different occurrences <strong>of</strong> a given concept<br />

or <strong>of</strong> a given word), just as much as personal supposition, <strong>the</strong>n it seems counterintuitive<br />

that only personal supposition should receive fur<strong>the</strong>r distinctions. In fact,<br />

Ockham’s and Buridan’s nominalism seems almost to require <strong>the</strong>se distinctions;<br />

for both <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, all that exists are <strong>the</strong> different actual occurrences <strong>of</strong> written,<br />

spoken and mental terms – that is, what we now call ‘tokens’, but not <strong>the</strong> corresponding<br />

types. For this reason, also in simple and material supposition it seems<br />

necessary to consider <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> entities (concepts, words) being talked about<br />

with a given proposition, just as much as with personal supposition.<br />

Buridan seemed to be well aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that one can quantify over <strong>the</strong><br />

different occurrences <strong>of</strong> a term. Take this passage, from <strong>the</strong> first treatise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Summulae:<br />

Next, we should say that if <strong>the</strong> subjects in <strong>the</strong> aforementioned propositions<br />

supposit materially, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition “[A] man is a species”<br />

is [. . . ] indefinite, for <strong>the</strong> term ‘man’ is not to be understood as suppositing<br />

only for itself, but indifferently for o<strong>the</strong>r similar terms as well<br />

[...]. And in this way “Every man is a species” would be universal,<br />

and “Some man is a species”, i.e. “Some term man is a species” would<br />

be particular, and “This man is a species”, i.e. “This term man is a<br />

species”, would be singular. [Buridan, 2001, 92] 27<br />

But Buridan does not go as far as actually applying <strong>the</strong> different modes <strong>of</strong> personal<br />

supposition to material supposition, even though from saying that a proposition<br />

is universal to acknowledging that its subject has confused and distributive supposition<br />

is but a small step (as it was widely recognized that <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> an<br />

affirmative universal proposition has confused and distributive supposition, and<br />

similarly that <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> a particular or indefinite supposition has determinate<br />

supposition and <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> a singular proposition has discrete supposition).<br />

To my knowledge, <strong>the</strong> first author to have made <strong>the</strong> small but significant step<br />

<strong>of</strong> introducing <strong>the</strong> distinctions originally pertaining only to personal supposition<br />

also to o<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> supposition is Buridan’s follower, Marsilius <strong>of</strong> Inghen. In his<br />

treatise on supposition [Marsilius <strong>of</strong> Inghen, 1983, pp. 52-97], Marsilius presents<br />

a compelling and elegant way <strong>of</strong> structuring <strong>the</strong> different kinds <strong>of</strong> supposition and<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir subdivisions. What is most remarkable about his doctrine is that, unlike his<br />

predecessors, who began by dividing proper supposition into personal, simple and<br />

material, Marsilius actually begins by <strong>the</strong> division <strong>of</strong> what were traditionally <strong>the</strong><br />

different modes <strong>of</strong> personal supposition. This is a sensible move, considering that<br />

27 I am indebted to Gyula Klima for having drawn my attention to this passage.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!