22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 149<br />

emerges only an indicator that this linkage is present, not as an explanation <strong>of</strong> how<br />

it is present. The Melidunenses seem to have a view which simply combines <strong>the</strong><br />

Abelardian and conventional approaches; <strong>the</strong>y claim that syllogisms are able to<br />

draw <strong>the</strong>ir strength not only from <strong>the</strong>ir formal arrangement but also from topical<br />

relations that exist between <strong>the</strong>ir terms [Green-Pedersen, 1987, p. 199]. The view<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Parvipontani on this matter is not presently known [Iwakuma, 2004, p.<br />

324].<br />

These are a few examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> school divisions which dominate <strong>the</strong> study<br />

<strong>of</strong> logic in <strong>the</strong> late twelfth century. Notice that <strong>the</strong>se examples have all issued<br />

from <strong>the</strong> more distinctively non-Aristotelian elements in Abelard’s work. On <strong>the</strong><br />

more conventional Arisotelian elements in logical <strong>the</strong>ory at this time that natural<br />

deference to authority might be expected to have produced more nuanced forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> disagreement, and perhaps more consensus. In fact scholarship has not yet<br />

uncovered equally compelling examples <strong>of</strong> four-way (or five-way, if one includes<br />

<strong>the</strong> Nominales) division on logical issues distinct from <strong>the</strong> ones on which Abelard<br />

was most innovative. If this remains <strong>the</strong> trend <strong>the</strong>n it will be testimony indeed to<br />

<strong>the</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s influence upon his contemporaries.<br />

The relationship <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schools is not exclusively one <strong>of</strong> mutual disagreement.<br />

The earliest systematic study into <strong>the</strong>ir relationship — found in L.M. de Rijk’s<br />

<strong>Logic</strong>a modernorum — in fact suggests certain <strong>the</strong>mes in common in <strong>the</strong>ir treatment<br />

<strong>of</strong> basic semantic <strong>the</strong>ory. While most recent research into this era has sought<br />

to distinguish <strong>the</strong> schools by charting opposing positions in debate, de Rijk has<br />

sought to discover how <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> twelfth century <strong>the</strong>ory ultimately leads<br />

to <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> terminist tradition in <strong>the</strong> thirteenth. His approach emphasizes<br />

<strong>the</strong>mes held in common by <strong>the</strong> schools, and <strong>the</strong> resulting analysis identifies<br />

two key lines <strong>of</strong> historical development.<br />

(i) First, and perhaps most importantly, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> increasing tendency to pay<br />

close attention to <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> context in determining meaning. De Rijk argues<br />

that this change is found in <strong>the</strong> grammatical <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> period. Eleventh<br />

century grammatical approaches are characterized by <strong>the</strong> belief that what <strong>the</strong> word<br />

means is what it was initially imposed to mean, not how it is used in particular<br />

contexts [de Rijk, 1967a, pp. 113-114]. Twelfth century approaches, with <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

growing interest in syntactic <strong>the</strong>ory, are more open to <strong>the</strong> idea that placement<br />

in a particular construction can legitimately influence a word’s meaning in that<br />

context [de Rijk, 1967a, pp. 115-17]. This approach is certainly to be found in<br />

Abelard’s work, and in his later glosses on Aristotle and his <strong>the</strong>ological works <strong>the</strong><br />

notion <strong>of</strong> translatio is regularly employed. By this term is meant some kind <strong>of</strong><br />

transferrence <strong>of</strong> meaning brought about by context, as in “<strong>the</strong> meadows smile,”<br />

where “smile” is used to mean “are flowering” [Abelard, 1921, p. 121 (29–35)].<br />

This is not an equivocal use, because equivocation involves a word’s having more<br />

than one imposed meaning, and that is not <strong>the</strong> case with “smile” here; it still has<br />

just one imposed meaning, and simply acquires ano<strong>the</strong>r temporary meaning when<br />

preceded by “<strong>the</strong> meadows.”<br />

Use <strong>of</strong> this notion <strong>of</strong> translatio as a staple <strong>of</strong> semantic <strong>the</strong>ory becomes fairly

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!