22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 519<br />

asked whe<strong>the</strong>r one should apply <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> possibility without qualification to<br />

divine possibilities and <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> qualified possibility, such as natural possibility,<br />

to those spoken <strong>of</strong> in accordance with <strong>the</strong> lower causes, or vice versa. 38 This is<br />

a sign <strong>of</strong> an increasing awareness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> conception <strong>of</strong> omnipotence,<br />

which included <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> eternal alternatives, was very different from philosophical<br />

modalities, and <strong>the</strong>re were some twelfth-century attempts to explicate <strong>the</strong> idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> synchronic alternatives more systematically.<br />

In addition to <strong>the</strong> doctrines <strong>of</strong> omnipotence and eternal choice between providential<br />

options, divine modalities were discussed in treating <strong>the</strong> compatibility <strong>of</strong><br />

divine omniscience and <strong>the</strong> contingency <strong>of</strong> events in <strong>the</strong> created world. In his<br />

longer commentary on De interpretatione, Boethius says <strong>of</strong> God that ‘he knows<br />

future events as happening contingently and not necessarily so that he does not<br />

ignore <strong>the</strong> possibility that something else might take place.’ 39 In his later work<br />

Consolation <strong>of</strong> Philosophy, Boethius argues that God is atemporal and has timeless<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> everything. God’s timelessness involves his having <strong>the</strong> whole history<br />

present to him simultaneously. God’s knowledge is not foreknowledge, since it is<br />

not temporally located, but <strong>the</strong> predictions <strong>of</strong> future contingents are true or false<br />

from <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> God’s eternal knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> things referred to. It<br />

is necessary that if God knows that p, <strong>the</strong>n p. This ‘conditional necessity’ does<br />

not imply <strong>the</strong> ‘simple necessity’ <strong>of</strong> p. 40 This approach was very influential and<br />

was fur<strong>the</strong>r developed in Aquinas’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> God who grasps all combinations <strong>of</strong><br />

things at particular times by one eternal vision. God has an immediate knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> all things and <strong>the</strong>ir relative temporal order, though none <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is past<br />

or future with respect to His cognition. The objects <strong>of</strong> divine omniscience are<br />

necessary by supposition (i.e., with respect to God’s knowledge and providential<br />

plan), but many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m are contingent with respect to <strong>the</strong>ir proximate causes. 41<br />

God’s eternal and immutable vision includes <strong>the</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> things which are<br />

future contingents in <strong>the</strong> temporal order, and he can supranaturally inform lower<br />

intellects about <strong>the</strong>se things – o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong>re could not be true prophetic predic-<br />

(Grottaferrata: Collegium S. Bonaventurae ad Claras Aquas, 1971-81), II.18.5-6; Simon <strong>of</strong> Tournai,<br />

Disputationes, ed. J. Warichez, Spicilegium Sacrum Lovaniense, Études et Documents 12<br />

(Louvain: Spicilegium Sacrum Lovaniense,1932), 35.2 (104.32-105.29); Peter <strong>of</strong> Poitiers, Sententiae,<br />

I.7 (65.444-66.452, 67.498-68.502); Alan <strong>of</strong> Lille, Regulae caelestis iuris, ed. N.M. Häring,<br />

Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 78 (1981), 164-5. This was <strong>the</strong> background<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scholastic doctrine <strong>of</strong> God’s absolute and ordained power. For similar discussions<br />

in medieval Arabic thought, see Kukkonen 2000.<br />

38William <strong>of</strong> Auxerre, Summa aurea, ed. J. Ribaillier, Spicilegium Bonaventurianum 16-20<br />

(Paris: Editions du CNRS and Rome: Collegium S. Bonaventurae ad Claras Aquas, 1980-86),<br />

I.11.2 (206-9).<br />

39In Periherm. II, 226.9-12.<br />

40Philosophiae consolatio, ed. L. Bieler, Corpus Christianorum Series Latina 94 (Turnhout:<br />

Brepols, 1957), V.6, 25-32; cf. Augustine, De civitate Dei XI.21. Boethius’s conception <strong>of</strong> God’s<br />

atemporal knowledge is meant to explain how future contingent events retain <strong>the</strong>ir indeterminateness<br />

while being certainly known as atemporally present. See also J. Marenbon, Boethius<br />

(New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 2003), 123-45.<br />

41Scriptum super libros Sententiarum, I.38.1.4-5; Summa contra gentiles, I.66-7; Quaestiones<br />

disputatae I: De veritate, 2.12; In Peri herm. I.14, 194-6; Summa <strong>the</strong>ologiae I.14.13.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!