22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

550 Simo Knuuttila<br />

physics. In arguing for <strong>the</strong> contingency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> created order Scotus writes:<br />

I do not call something contingent because it is not always or necessarily<br />

<strong>the</strong> case, but because <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> it could be actual at <strong>the</strong><br />

very moment when it occurs. 164<br />

This is a denial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present and <strong>the</strong><br />

temporal frequency characterization <strong>of</strong> contingency. In <strong>the</strong> Scotist definition, <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> contingency is spelt out by considering simultaneous<br />

alternatives. What is actual is contingent only if, instead <strong>of</strong> being actual, it could<br />

be not actual. This conception <strong>of</strong> simultaneous contingent alternatives is part <strong>of</strong><br />

an argument that <strong>the</strong> first cause does not act necessarily. According to Scotus, <strong>the</strong><br />

eternal creative act <strong>of</strong> divine will is free only if it is a choice between alternatives<br />

and could be o<strong>the</strong>r than it is in a real sense. 165<br />

That God acts by choice between alternatives had been a common <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

view since Augustine, but Scotus formulated its conceptual foundation in a new<br />

way, which had consequences for how modal terms in general were understood.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Augustinian tradition, it was thought that metaphysical possibilities are<br />

ultimately based on <strong>the</strong> divine essence and represent <strong>the</strong> ways in which it could be<br />

imitated by created things. Scotus was <strong>the</strong> first to deviate from this metaphysical<br />

tradition in which possibilities are founded on divine being. According to Scotus,<br />

when God as an omniscient being knows all possibilities, he does not know <strong>the</strong>m<br />

by turning first to his essence. Possibilities can be known in <strong>the</strong>mselves. 166 In<br />

fact <strong>the</strong>y would be what <strong>the</strong>y are even if <strong>the</strong>re were no God. Scotus states that<br />

if it is assumed that, per impossibile, nei<strong>the</strong>r God nor <strong>the</strong> world exists and that<br />

<strong>the</strong> proposition ’The world is possible’ <strong>the</strong>n existed, this proposition would be<br />

true. The actual world is possible as it is, and this possibility and <strong>the</strong> possibilities<br />

<strong>of</strong> unrealized things are primary metaphysical facts which are not dependent on<br />

anything else. 167<br />

Scotus calls <strong>the</strong> propositional formulations <strong>of</strong> pure possibilities logical possibilities<br />

(possibile logicum). These express things and states <strong>of</strong> affairs to which it is<br />

not repugnant to be, which means that <strong>the</strong>ir descriptions do not involve a contradiction.<br />

Possibilities as such have no kind <strong>of</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own, but are real<br />

in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>y form <strong>the</strong> precondition for everything that is or can be. 168<br />

A great deal <strong>of</strong> Scotus’s discussion <strong>of</strong> metaphysical <strong>the</strong>mes concentrates on <strong>the</strong><br />

164 Ordinatio I.2.1.1-2, 86 (Opera omnia, vol. 2);De primo principio, ed. and translated by W.<br />

Kluxen (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1974), IV.4.<br />

165 Lectura I.39.1-5, 58; see also L. Honnefelder, Duns Scotus ((Munich: C.H. Beck, 2005), 85-6.<br />

166 Ord. I.35, 32 (Opera omnia, vol. 6); Knuuttila 1993, 103-4; S. Knuuttila, ’Duns Scotus and<br />

<strong>the</strong> Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>al Modalities’ in L. Honnefelder, R. Wood, M. Dreyer (eds.), John Duns<br />

Scotus: Metaphysics and Ethics, Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 53<br />

(Leiden: Brill, 1996), 135-36.<br />

167 Ord. I.7.1, 27 (Opera omnia, vol. 4);;Lect.I.7, 32 (Opera omnia, vol. 16); Lect.; I.39.1-5,<br />

49; Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis libri VI-IX, ed. R. Andrews et al. (St.<br />

Bonaventure: The Franciscan Institute, St. Bonaventure <strong>University</strong>, 1997), 9.1-2, 18.<br />

168 Knuuttila 1996, 137-41.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!