22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

186 Terence Parsons<br />

For example, ‘he begins to be healthy’ — he is [healthy] and he was<br />

not [healthy] earlier; ‘he ceases to be sick’ — he is not sick [and he was<br />

sick earlier].<br />

Appeals to exponibles <strong>of</strong>ten turn up when some topic is being discussed where<br />

a certain sentence seems to be a counterexample to a proposal under discussion,<br />

or where it is not clear what a certain proposal would say about <strong>the</strong> example.<br />

Expounding yields a new form that fits with <strong>the</strong> proposal. In general it seems to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong> semantics <strong>of</strong> an exponible proposition is taken to be whatever<br />

is <strong>the</strong> semantics <strong>of</strong> its expounded version. 37<br />

3.1 Signification<br />

3 SIGNIFICATION AND SUPPOSITION<br />

There are different <strong>the</strong>ories about how language relates to <strong>the</strong> world. I concentrate<br />

here on two accounts that were commonly appealed to by semanticists. One is an<br />

older realist account that appeals to real universals. The o<strong>the</strong>r appeals instead to<br />

mental concepts.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> realist account, <strong>the</strong>re are universals existing outside <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind, with<br />

individual things falling under <strong>the</strong>m. These universals are usually called forms.<br />

A common term gets into <strong>the</strong> language by being conventionally imposed on a<br />

common form. For example, <strong>the</strong> term ‘donkey’ is imposed on a certain form (<strong>the</strong><br />

species, donkey), which is shared by all donkeys. This imposition is ei<strong>the</strong>r done<br />

by <strong>the</strong> will <strong>of</strong> a speaker, or, more usually, is done by convention (with details not<br />

given). As a result, <strong>the</strong> word is a sign <strong>of</strong>, or signifies, that form. Signification is <strong>the</strong><br />

basic semantic notion; it is a kind <strong>of</strong> meaning that a word possesses independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> any particular use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word. A sign is also said to (indirectly) signify <strong>the</strong><br />

things that share in <strong>the</strong> form, so that ‘donkey’ is also said to (indirectly) signify<br />

each and every individual donkey:<br />

word<br />

signifies<br />

form<br />

indirectly signifies<br />

is shared by<br />

individuals<br />

On a nominalist account, <strong>the</strong>re are no universals existing outside <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind.<br />

Instead, <strong>the</strong>re are concepts in <strong>the</strong> mind that naturally are concepts <strong>of</strong> various<br />

individuals. (This view is <strong>of</strong>ten backed up by an epistemological <strong>the</strong>ory about<br />

37 But see section 7.8 for an exception to this principle.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!