22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Developments in <strong>the</strong> Fifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries 641<br />

tain and rhetoric, freer. 154 As he had remarked earlier, a good dialectical pro<strong>of</strong><br />

could not be o<strong>the</strong>rwise, but a rhetorical pro<strong>of</strong> can always be put ano<strong>the</strong>r way. 155<br />

In <strong>the</strong> section on Topics, however, he takes up <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> signs, which he divides<br />

into necessary and probable. 156 He also uses an explicit probability operator, placing<br />

‘probabile est igitur’ in front <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conclusion <strong>of</strong> an argument from probable<br />

signs.He <strong>the</strong>n links <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> signs with <strong>the</strong> personal Topics, saying that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are both less relevant to <strong>the</strong> dialectician, who needs necessary and evident<br />

arguments, than to <strong>the</strong> rhetorician, but <strong>the</strong>ir discussion should not be left to <strong>the</strong><br />

rhetorician. Arguments using premisses based on signs or <strong>the</strong> personal Topics need<br />

to be put into <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> syllogisms, enthymemes, induction or example. For instance,<br />

he gives <strong>the</strong> argument: “It is unlikely (verisimile non est) that students <strong>of</strong><br />

literature should indulge in pleasures, Coelius is a student <strong>of</strong> literature, <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

it is unlikely that he indulges in pleasures.” The example suggests that he wanted<br />

to treat probability operators as part <strong>of</strong> a deductive system, ra<strong>the</strong>r than using<br />

<strong>the</strong>m to construct a non-deductive probabilistic logic.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Erotemata Dialectices, enthymeme is linked with signs, and Melanchthon<br />

explains that Aristotle defined enthymeme as an imperfect syllogism whose premisses<br />

are probabilities (ex icotibus) and signs. 157 However, <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> discussing<br />

true-seeming (verisimilia) signs is only to warn us against misleading and fallacious<br />

arguments. In <strong>the</strong> section on Topics, signs are now discussed quite separately<br />

from <strong>the</strong> personal Topics, and are divided into those that are necessary and those<br />

that are “not necessary but are associated accidents”, called ‘eikota’. 158 We have<br />

to be very careful using arguments based on <strong>the</strong> latter, lest we deceive ourselves,<br />

as <strong>of</strong>ten happens “in suspicionibus et aliis malis persuasionibus.” We should remind<br />

ourselves here that suspicio and persuasion belong to rhetoric. All in all,<br />

Melanchthon, despite clear humanist interests, does not write like a logician who<br />

is intent on legitimatizing informal, probabilistic argumentation.<br />

Agostino Nifo firmly relegates one kind <strong>of</strong> enthymeme to rhetoric. In his Dialectica<br />

ludicra, he quotes Michael Psellus, an eleventh-century Byzantine writer,<br />

whose work on rhetoric divided consequences into necessary and contingent. 159<br />

The latter were those that merely persuade without proving or convincing, such<br />

as rhetorical enthymeme and example. Nifo went on to claim that <strong>the</strong>re are two<br />

sorts <strong>of</strong> enthymeme, <strong>the</strong> analytical enthymeme which differs from a syllogism only<br />

in that it uses one premiss, and <strong>the</strong> rhetorical enthymeme, which differs from a<br />

syllogism both in its use <strong>of</strong> just one premiss and in <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> suppressed<br />

premiss is nei<strong>the</strong>r necessary nor probable but merely true-seeming (verisimilis). 160<br />

Such a premiss is not dependent on opinion or fact, but on a link with action. 161<br />

154 Melanchthon, Compendiaria Dialectices Ratio, col. 743.<br />

155 Melanchthon, Compendiaria Dialectices Ratio, col. 733.<br />

156 Melanchthon, Compendiaria Dialectices Ratio, cols. 750–751.<br />

157 Melanchthon, Erotemata Dialectices, cols. 617–619.<br />

158 Melanchthon, Erotemata Dialectices, cols. 704–706.<br />

159 Niphus, Dialectica ludicra, f. 110 va.<br />

160 Niphus, Dialectica ludicra, f. 110 vb–111 ra.<br />

161 Niphus, Dialectica ludicra, f. 111 ra: “assumptio verisimilis non accipitur ab opinionem: vel

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!