22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

610 E. Jennifer Ashworth<br />

that <strong>of</strong> imitating <strong>the</strong> written texts <strong>of</strong> men who had been dead for fifteen centuries. 4<br />

To understand <strong>the</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se developments for <strong>the</strong> logician, we have to<br />

consider three questions. First, how much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> medieval logic described in <strong>the</strong><br />

previous chapters survived? Second, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as medieval logic survived, were <strong>the</strong>re<br />

any interesting new developments in it? 5 Third, does humanist logic <strong>of</strong>fer an<br />

interesting alternative to medieval logic?<br />

In Part One <strong>of</strong> this chapter I shall consider <strong>the</strong> first two questions in <strong>the</strong> context<br />

<strong>of</strong> a historical overview in which I trace developments in logic from <strong>the</strong> later middle<br />

ages through to 1606, <strong>the</strong> year in which <strong>the</strong> Jesuits <strong>of</strong> Coimbra published <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

great commentary on Aristotle’s logical works, <strong>the</strong> Commentarii Conimbricensis<br />

in Dialecticam Aristotelis. 6 I shall begin by considering <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian logical<br />

corpus, <strong>the</strong> six books <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Organon, and <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> commentaries on<br />

this work. I shall <strong>the</strong>n examine <strong>the</strong> fate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> specifically medieval contributions<br />

to logic. Finally, I shall discuss <strong>the</strong> textbook tradition, and <strong>the</strong> ways in which<br />

textbooks changed and developed during <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century. I shall argue that<br />

<strong>the</strong> medieval tradition in logic co-existed for some time with <strong>the</strong> new humanism,<br />

that <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century is dominated by Aristotelianism, and that what emerged<br />

at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century was not so much a humanist logic as a simplified<br />

Aristotelian logic.<br />

In Part Two <strong>of</strong> this chapter, I shall ask whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> claims made about humanist<br />

logic and its novel contributions to probabilistic and informal logic have any<br />

foundation. I shall argue that ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong>re is any principled discussion <strong>of</strong> such<br />

matters, it is to be found among writers in <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian tradition.<br />

4For its deleterious effects, see Giard, “Du latin médiéval”, p. 46. For more about <strong>the</strong> humanist<br />

return to <strong>the</strong> past, see W. Keith Percival, “Grammar and Rhetoric in <strong>the</strong> Renaissance” in<br />

Renaissance Eloquence. Studies in <strong>the</strong> Theory and Practice <strong>of</strong> Renaissance Rhetoric, ed. James<br />

J. Murphy (Berkeley: <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1983), pp. 303–330, especially pp. 311–312.<br />

See also Brian P. Copenhaver, “Translation, terminology and style in philosophical discourse” in<br />

The Cambridge <strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong> Renaissance Philosophy, ed. Charles B. Schmitt, Quentin Skinner,<br />

and Eckhard Kessler, (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1988), pp. 77–110, especially<br />

pp. 104–106. For humanist innovations in logical vocabulary, see G. Nuchelmans, Late-Scholastic<br />

and Humanist Theories <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Proposition (Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Company,<br />

1980), part two, passim.<br />

5For a full account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se matters, I refer <strong>the</strong> reader to my own writings, in particular:<br />

E.J. Ashworth, Language and <strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Post-Medieval Period (Dordrecht, Boston: D. Reidel,<br />

1974); E. J. Ashworth, “Traditional logic” in The Cambridge <strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong> Renaissance Philosophy,<br />

pp. 143–172; E. J. Ashworth, introduction to Robert Sanderson, <strong>Logic</strong>ae Artis Compendium, ed.<br />

E. J. Ashworth (Bologna: Editrice CLUEB, 1985), pp. XI–LV.<br />

6An unauthorized edition appeared earlier, in 1604. The author <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic commentary was<br />

Sebastian de Couto.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!