22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

86 Ian Wilks<br />

are <strong>the</strong>se items corresponding to <strong>the</strong> subject and predicate terms? Speaking <strong>of</strong><br />

animal instead <strong>of</strong> animals is to use a mass noun where we would normally use a<br />

count noun. We know what animals are, but what is animal?<br />

Notice how easily a Platonist can give a response. Animal can be taken as <strong>the</strong><br />

form <strong>of</strong> animality which all animals share, and in which <strong>the</strong>y all participate. Man<br />

can be taken as <strong>the</strong> shared form <strong>of</strong> humanity (or manness) common to all men.<br />

Animal and man, taken thus, are single, distinct things, and are appropriately<br />

denoted by unpluralized nouns. The above propositions just describe in various<br />

ways, some true, some false, <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong>se single, distinct things.<br />

So in this way <strong>the</strong> conventional language <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> categorical syllogism fairly<br />

invites some kind <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> shared forms — forms which exist independently <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> things that none<strong>the</strong>less share in <strong>the</strong>m. 7 And this is why Porphyry’s Isagoge,<br />

intended as a propaedutic to <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> logic, begins with <strong>the</strong>se questions about<br />

genera and species: “(1) Whe<strong>the</strong>r genera or species exist in <strong>the</strong>mselves or reside in<br />

mere concepts alone; (2) whe<strong>the</strong>r, if <strong>the</strong>y exist, <strong>the</strong>y are corporeal or incorporeal;<br />

and (3) whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y exist apart or in sense objects and in dependence on <strong>the</strong>m”<br />

[Porphyry, 1975, pp. 27 (12)–28 (14)]. Aristotle himself did not ultimately accept<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> shared forms, but bequea<strong>the</strong>d a language which made <strong>the</strong>m a live<br />

issue. 8 Abelard could not avoid having some position on this issue.<br />

He in fact did not accept <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> shared forms ei<strong>the</strong>r. Some people,<br />

he says, “maintain that <strong>the</strong> same thing is essentially in many, so that <strong>the</strong> same<br />

thing that is in this is essentially in that, although is furnished<br />

with different forms. For example animal is in Socrates and in Brunellus and in<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs” [Abelard, 1933, p. 515 (17–21)]. 9 So animal is shared by all animals;<br />

in o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong>y are all essentially <strong>the</strong> same animal because <strong>the</strong> form that<br />

confers animality upon <strong>the</strong>m is <strong>the</strong> same form. Accordingly, “Socrates is in no<br />

way essentially different from Brunellus” [Abelard, 1933, p. 515 (23–24)]. Abelard<br />

has a number <strong>of</strong> objections against this view [Abelard, 1933, pp. 515 (32)–518 (8)];<br />

<strong>the</strong>se emphasize <strong>the</strong> counter-intuitiveness <strong>of</strong> what it implies about individuality<br />

– such as its implication that Socrates and Brunellus <strong>the</strong> ass are essentially <strong>the</strong><br />

same animal, since <strong>the</strong>y share <strong>the</strong> same form <strong>of</strong> animality. Shared forms make<br />

individuality impossible. The fact that individuals do exist entails that shared<br />

forms do not.<br />

Abelard is perfectly willing to speak <strong>of</strong> forms/genera/species, but not as accompanied<br />

by anything like a Platonic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> participation. While he does<br />

7 By contrast, a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> unshared forms posits distinct forms for distinct things. On this<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong> animality <strong>of</strong> one animal is distinct from <strong>the</strong> animality <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r animal. See note<br />

10 below.<br />

8 The relationship between Aristotle’s syllogistic and Plato’s method <strong>of</strong> division (for which,<br />

see [Kneale and Kneale, 1962, pp. 44, 67–68]) would explain how Aristotle came to bequeath<br />

such a language.<br />

9 Abelard is describing <strong>the</strong> position now referred to as “Material Essence Realism.” This<br />

position is associated with William <strong>of</strong> Champeaux, and articulates in some detail a metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> shared forms. For Material Essence Realism, and Abelard’s critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> position, see<br />

[Tweedale, 1976, pp. 95–111], [Gracia, 1984, pp. 198–200], and [King, 2004, pp. 66–69]. For<br />

Abelard’s complex relationship to Platonism generally, see [Marenbon, 1997b].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!