22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Nominalist Semantics <strong>of</strong> Ockham and Buridan 405<br />

and <strong>the</strong> signification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate, exists just in case <strong>the</strong> ultimate significate<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate in <strong>the</strong> suppositum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject, i.e., Homer’s blindness exists.<br />

The existence <strong>of</strong> this, however, is conditioned on <strong>the</strong> non-actuality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ultimate<br />

significatum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> corresponding positive predicate, namely, <strong>the</strong> non-existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> Homer’s sight. Thus, <strong>the</strong> simple fact <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition ‘Homer<br />

is blind’ will consist in <strong>the</strong> simple fact <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> significatum <strong>of</strong> this<br />

proposition. However, <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> significatum <strong>of</strong> this proposition is conditioned<br />

on <strong>the</strong> existence or non-existence <strong>of</strong> several “layers” <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r items, assigned<br />

as <strong>the</strong> various semantic values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic components <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition.<br />

And herein reside both <strong>the</strong> strength and <strong>the</strong> difficulty <strong>of</strong> this semantic construction.<br />

The primary strength <strong>of</strong> this construction consists in <strong>the</strong> expressive power<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system, which renders it capable <strong>of</strong> making <strong>the</strong> most refined distinctions,<br />

and thus allowing <strong>the</strong> formulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most abstruse metaphysical questions<br />

concerning <strong>the</strong> various semantic values <strong>of</strong> any phrases in any syntactical category.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, this is also <strong>the</strong> difficulty with this construction. It not only allows<br />

<strong>the</strong> formulation <strong>of</strong> abstruse metaphysical questions: it makes <strong>the</strong>m inevitable,<br />

especially concerning <strong>the</strong> identity and distinction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se semantic values and <strong>the</strong><br />

determination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir nature, <strong>the</strong>ir precise ontological status.<br />

OCKHAM’S COMPLAINTS<br />

In fact, <strong>the</strong> apparently inevitable obscurity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issues concerning <strong>the</strong> multitude<br />

and distinctions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se semantic values was <strong>the</strong> best motivation for Ockham to get<br />

rid <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m in one fell swoop, by discarding <strong>the</strong> semantics that engendered <strong>the</strong>m in<br />

<strong>the</strong> first place. Ockham’s main complaints against <strong>the</strong> semantics <strong>of</strong> “<strong>the</strong> moderns”<br />

as he ra<strong>the</strong>r tendentiously refers to <strong>the</strong> representatives <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> older <strong>the</strong>ory 34 fall<br />

precisely into <strong>the</strong>se two categories: those concerning <strong>the</strong> sheer multitude <strong>of</strong> entities<br />

(or quasi-entities) implied by this construction, clearly <strong>of</strong>fending a nominalist’s<br />

“taste for desert landscapes” (as Quine famously put it), and those concerning<br />

<strong>the</strong> obscurity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature and distinctions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se entities. The arguments<br />

supporting <strong>the</strong>se complaints are also <strong>of</strong> two main sorts: <strong>the</strong>re are those that argue<br />

for <strong>the</strong> absurdity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ontological commitments <strong>of</strong> his opponents, and those that<br />

argue for <strong>the</strong> eliminability <strong>of</strong> those commitments.<br />

The first strategy points to a number <strong>of</strong> logical and physical absurdities that<br />

seem to follow if we allow “multiplying entities with <strong>the</strong> multiplication <strong>of</strong> terms”,<br />

as Ockham claims <strong>the</strong> “moderns” do. 35 To be sure, as we have seen, Ockham’s<br />

characterization <strong>of</strong> his opponents’ position is not entirely fair, for <strong>the</strong>y are not<br />

34 In <strong>the</strong> medieval intellectual context, to be “modern” is to carry lesser weight than <strong>the</strong> established<br />

older authorities. Thus, by referring to his opponents as “moderns” Ockham was trying<br />

to “sell” his innovations as being just an attempt to restore a simpler, original Aristotelianism<br />

distorted by <strong>the</strong> unnecessary additions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “moderns”.<br />

35 Ockham, W. Summa logicae (SL), Philo<strong>the</strong>us Boehner, Gedeon Gál and Stephen F. Brown,<br />

ed., (“Opera philosophica,” vol. 1), St. Bonaventure, NY: The Franciscan Institute, 1974, p.<br />

171.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!