22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

138 Ian Wilks<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 493 (12)] but also “Ei<strong>the</strong>r this is hot, or it is cold or tepid”<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 493 (19)] as allowable readings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> original. Of course on his<br />

account <strong>the</strong>se cannot be viewed as having exactly <strong>the</strong> same meaning, because in<br />

<strong>the</strong> former <strong>the</strong> merely truth functional relation exists between <strong>the</strong> first and second<br />

disjuncts (hot and cold), while in <strong>the</strong> latter it exists between <strong>the</strong> second and third<br />

(cold and tepid). However subtle, this must be taken as making a difference in <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole.<br />

How we group <strong>the</strong> disjuncts in a proposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form (p ∨ q ∨ r) is intuitively<br />

thought not to make a difference to <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole compound disjunction,<br />

but Abelard’s analysis suggests o<strong>the</strong>rwise. So this is itself a counter-intuitive<br />

result. His initial account <strong>of</strong> stronger, non-truth-functional disjunction makes it<br />

difficult to incorporate that connective into nested contexts. As we shall now see,<br />

he encounters a similarly counter-intuitive result with <strong>the</strong> conditional, where again<br />

he must have recourse to a secondary and weaker version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> connective in order<br />

to deal with nested propositional structures.<br />

Consider <strong>the</strong> conditional “If it is not well <strong>the</strong>n it is sick.” This proposition is<br />

false, given that anything, including rocks, can fail to be well; but only living things<br />

(in Abelard’s view) can be sick. So failing to be well does not imply sickness. But<br />

failing to be well among animals does seem to imply sickness, so it seems plausible<br />

that if we write <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> being an animal into <strong>the</strong> conditional in question<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> result will be true. It is <strong>the</strong>refore tempting to apply a qualifying “if”<br />

clause: “If it is an animal, it follows that if it is not well <strong>the</strong>n it is sick.” Abelard<br />

argues, however, that <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> such qualification, whe<strong>the</strong>r it takes this form<br />

or o<strong>the</strong>rs, will not be true, given <strong>the</strong> requirements for implication. He considers<br />

three cases, none <strong>of</strong> which he finds satisfactory. (i) “If it is an animal, it follows<br />

that if is not well <strong>the</strong>n it is sick.” This attempt attaches <strong>the</strong> qualification to <strong>the</strong><br />

whole conditional, and makes that conditional <strong>the</strong> consequent in <strong>the</strong> larger one<br />

that results from <strong>the</strong> attachment. But we know that <strong>the</strong> conditional standing<br />

as <strong>the</strong> consequent taken by itself is false (“If it is not well <strong>the</strong>n it is sick”). So<br />

if <strong>the</strong> antecedent is true <strong>the</strong>n we have a true antecedent and a false consequent<br />

— rendering false <strong>the</strong> compound conditional taken as a whole when said <strong>of</strong> an<br />

animal [Abelard, 1970, p. 402 (14–15)]. (ii) “If it is not well it follows that<br />

if it is an animal it is sick.” Here <strong>the</strong> qualifying “if” clause is attached to <strong>the</strong><br />

consequent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> original. But “If it is an animal, it is sick” cannot be true<br />

since <strong>the</strong>re are many animals that are not sick; animality and sickness are not in<br />

<strong>the</strong> right relation to make that conditional true. So again here <strong>the</strong> consequent<br />

is false, and so if <strong>the</strong> antecedent is true <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> compound conditional as a<br />

whole is false [Abelard, 1970, p. 402 (21–23)]. (iii) “(If it is an animal <strong>the</strong>n<br />

it is not well) that it is sick.” This attempt attaches <strong>the</strong> qualifying<br />

“if” clause to <strong>the</strong> antececent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> original conditional. But what we have here<br />

is <strong>the</strong> claim that a categorical proposition follows from a conditional one. This<br />

claim cannot be true, [Abelard, 1970, p. 402 (26–27)], presumably because <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> existential presupposition expressed in <strong>the</strong> categorical, which is absent from

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!