22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 113<br />

<strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> possibility involved here is understood, it is clear that <strong>the</strong> de re<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> example proposition allows it to be true, and <strong>the</strong> de sensu reading<br />

does not.<br />

This is not an argument for <strong>the</strong> superiority <strong>of</strong> de re readings <strong>of</strong> modal propositions,<br />

since, as Abelard notes, <strong>the</strong> opposite result holds for “It is necessary for<br />

<strong>the</strong> standing man not to sit.” This is true taken de sensu (since “The standing<br />

man does not sit” is necessarily true) and false taken de re (since it is false that<br />

<strong>the</strong> standing man necessarily does not sit) [Abelard, 1958, p. 14 (8–13); Abelard,<br />

2006, 12.19]. Both this example and <strong>the</strong> previous one simply convey how very different<br />

<strong>the</strong> two readings are. Never<strong>the</strong>less, Abelard does prefer <strong>the</strong> de re approach.<br />

The problem with <strong>the</strong> de sensu approach is that it makes modal propositions into<br />

impersonal propositions; <strong>the</strong>se, as we have seen, lack a referring subject term and<br />

as such lack features like universality, particularity, and ability to convert, and<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore fit poorly into <strong>the</strong> forms and figures <strong>of</strong> syllogistic logic. We can compare<br />

<strong>the</strong> standing <strong>of</strong> impersonals in this regard to <strong>the</strong> standing <strong>of</strong> relational propositions.<br />

These likewise fit poorly into <strong>the</strong> forms and figures, and need to be re-cast<br />

somehow into conventional subject-predicate syntax. As <strong>the</strong>y stand, prior to this<br />

change, <strong>the</strong>y are perfectly coherent propositions, capable <strong>of</strong> being true or false;<br />

but from a syllogistic perspective, <strong>the</strong>ir limitation is that <strong>the</strong>y are not perspicuous<br />

expressions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir content. This would seem to be Abelard’s view about<br />

impersonals generally and, more specifically, about de sensu modals.<br />

But <strong>the</strong>re is a more technical limitation to be observed in de sensu modals.<br />

The infinitival propositions in which <strong>the</strong>y are expressed <strong>of</strong>fer two different points<br />

at which negations may be inserted. “It is possible for Socrates to run” can be<br />

negated as a whole: “It is not possible for Socrates to run.” But <strong>the</strong> infinitival<br />

portion, since it involves a verb, can be negated as well: “It is possible for Socrates<br />

not to run.” Abelard notes that this second negation in fact makes sense only on<br />

a de re reading. On a de sensu reading <strong>the</strong> infinitival phrase “for Socrates to run”<br />

is <strong>of</strong> course <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition. Now one does not negate a proposition<br />

by negating its subject term; for example, one does not regard “Non-Socrates is<br />

running” as being a negated form <strong>of</strong> “Socrates is running.” So one must likewise<br />

not regard “It is possible for Socrates not to run,” taken de sensu, as being a<br />

negated form <strong>of</strong> “It is possible for Socrates to run”; again, <strong>the</strong> subject term on<br />

this de sensu reading is “for Socrates to run,” and that is what <strong>the</strong> sign <strong>of</strong> negation<br />

has just been applied to. The conclusion is that <strong>the</strong> de re reading engenders a<br />

class <strong>of</strong> negated forms which vanish when <strong>the</strong> reading is de sensu. In fact <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are three forms <strong>of</strong> de re negation: <strong>the</strong> two just mentioned (“It is not possible for<br />

Socrates to run”; “It is possible for Socrates not to run”) and <strong>the</strong>ir combination:<br />

“It is not possible for Socrates not to run.” In being able to capture only one <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>se three, <strong>the</strong> de sensu reading must be taken as comparatively less expressive<br />

[Abelard, 1958, p. 21 (22)–22 (15); Abelard, 2006, 12.38–39].<br />

When quantifiers are attached and varied, <strong>the</strong>se four de re forms (<strong>the</strong> origi-<br />

played some role in his thought.” Marenbon argues that nei<strong>the</strong>r approach captures Abelard’s<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modal operators [Marenbon, 1991; Marenbon, 1997a, pp. 221–223].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!