22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

488 Catarina Dutilh Novaes<br />

begins. Then O puts forward a fur<strong>the</strong>r proposition, R responds to it according to<br />

R(φn), and this procedure is repeated until <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> game.<br />

The logical rules <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> game are defined by R(φn), in <strong>the</strong> following way:<br />

DEFINITION 2 (Rules for positum).<br />

R(φ0) =0iffφ0 62 ⊥<br />

R(φ0) =1iffφ0 ⊥<br />

The rule defining <strong>the</strong> response that R should give to φ0 (<strong>the</strong> positum — [Burley,<br />

1988, 378]) has interesting consequences for <strong>the</strong> idea that obligationes are games <strong>of</strong><br />

consistency maintenance. If R is obliged to accept at <strong>the</strong> beginning a proposition<br />

that entails a contradiction — for example, any paradoxical proposition such as<br />

Liar sentences and <strong>the</strong> like — <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is no possible winning strategy for R.<br />

He cannot maintain <strong>the</strong> consistency <strong>of</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> propositions that, from <strong>the</strong> outset,<br />

contains a contradictory paradoxical proposition. So <strong>the</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> game stipulate<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re always be a winning strategy for R, starting from this restriction<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> positum. Burley expresses this clause by saying that it must be in <strong>the</strong><br />

Respondent’s power to satisfy <strong>the</strong> requirement (<strong>of</strong> not falling in contradiction) (cf.<br />

[Burley, 1988, 376]).<br />

DEFINITION 3 (Rules for proposita).<br />

<br />

Γn−1 φn, or<br />

R(ϕn) =1iff<br />

Γn−1 φn, Γn−1 ¬φn and Kc 63 φn<br />

<br />

Γn−1 ¬φn, or<br />

R(φn) =0iff<br />

Γn−1 φn, Γn−1 ¬φn and KC ¬φn<br />

R(φ)n) =?iffΓn−1 φn, Γn−1 ¬φn,KC φn,KC ¬φn<br />

That is, if Respondent fails to recognize inferential relations and if he does not<br />

respond to a proposition according to its truth-value within common knowledge,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n he responds badly (cf. [Burley, 1988, 381]).<br />

Formation <strong>of</strong> Γn. The different sets <strong>of</strong> propositions accepted by R (i.e., <strong>the</strong><br />

propositions to which R has committed himself in <strong>the</strong> disputation) are formed in<br />

<strong>the</strong> following way:<br />

DEFINITION 4 (The sets Γn).<br />

If R(φn) = 1, <strong>the</strong>n Γn =Γn−1 ∪{φn}<br />

62 I use <strong>the</strong> forcing turnstyle throughout to express <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> semantic implication<br />

between propositions. That is, within obligationes <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> ‘following’ is not defined<br />

syntactically or pro<strong>of</strong>-<strong>the</strong>oretically, but ra<strong>the</strong>r semantically.<br />

63 In case <strong>of</strong> KC, it is not so much that KC semantically implies a proposition φn, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

that φn is contained in KC (<strong>the</strong>refore a fortiori KC also implies φn). For <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> simplicity,<br />

I use only <strong>the</strong> forcing turnstyle.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!