22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

102 Ian Wilks<br />

fail to achieve propositionality. If <strong>the</strong>y are grouped in accordance with grammatical<br />

rules <strong>of</strong> construction <strong>the</strong>y may constitute an appropriate conjunction <strong>of</strong> words, a<br />

competens dictionum coniunctio [Abelard, 1970, p. 147 (28)]. But this is no<br />

guarantee that <strong>the</strong>y will constitute a proposition. A proposition is a complete<br />

phrase, an oratio perfecta 38 ; what indicates <strong>the</strong> incompleteness <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r phrases<br />

is <strong>the</strong> disposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hearer to pause and “desire to hear something more”<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 148 (27-28)]. When words grouped according to grammatical<br />

rules suffice to meet this desire, we have a proposition. The key element is <strong>of</strong><br />

course <strong>the</strong> verb. “Without <strong>the</strong> verb,” says Abelard, “<strong>the</strong>re is no completion <strong>of</strong><br />

sense” [Abelard, 1970, p. 148 (29–30)].<br />

Mere combinations <strong>of</strong> names do not yield this completion. What <strong>the</strong>y yield is<br />

something that, under conditions <strong>of</strong> grammatical appropriateness, simply remains<br />

at <strong>the</strong> semantic level <strong>of</strong> a name. “Rational, mortal animal” functions grammatically<br />

just as “man” does, even though <strong>the</strong> one is a phrase and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r a word.<br />

This naming function is brought about in <strong>the</strong> former case by a more complex<br />

internal structure <strong>of</strong> signification, involving more mental acts (actus intellectus)<br />

than <strong>the</strong> latter, but in <strong>the</strong> end both perform as names, and in fact as names <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> same thing [Abelard, 1927, p. 325 (24–29); Abelard, 2006, 01.94; Nuchelmans,<br />

1973, p. 143]. At this level no considerations <strong>of</strong> truth or falsity arise. Names and<br />

incomplete phrases may have application to things or fail to do so, but this just<br />

means that <strong>the</strong>y are ei<strong>the</strong>r sound (sanus) or not [Abelard, 1927, p. 326 (30–36);<br />

Abelard, 2006, 01.97]. 39 “The running man” signifies in such a way that it is able<br />

to name, and as such is described as being sound. But it is not appropriately said<br />

to be true. It differs from “<strong>the</strong> man runs” by <strong>the</strong> fact that in using it we determine<br />

“running . . . as adjacent to man, but we do not also assert <strong>the</strong> adjacence, which<br />

cannot be done without a verb” [Abelard, 1970, p. 149 (12–14)].<br />

The verb’s special ability to confer completeness <strong>of</strong> sense resides in its ability to<br />

convey predicative force. The example <strong>of</strong> predicative force given above is assertive<br />

force, <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> which is a proposition. But Abelard notes that <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> predicative force as well, which yield o<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> complete phrase.<br />

One can predicate interrogatively or imperatively; in uttering a prayer we have a<br />

fourth different sort <strong>of</strong> predication, and in uttering a wish a fifth [Abelard, 1970,<br />

p. 151 (4-14)]. These five kinds <strong>of</strong> complete phrase represent five different ways <strong>of</strong><br />

joining predicate to subject, and <strong>of</strong> demonstrating “<strong>the</strong> inherence <strong>of</strong> something in<br />

something in accordance with various dispositions (affectus) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul” [Abelard,<br />

1970, p. 149 (21–22)]. 40 What is at issue here is <strong>the</strong> distinction between sentential<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory: “maximal proposition.” Note that Abelard takes <strong>the</strong> token quality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> propositio so<br />

seriously that he actually denies what we know as <strong>the</strong> “Tarski biconditional”; from <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

a man exists it does not follow that “A man exists” is true, since “A man exists” might never<br />

have been uttered [Abelard, 1921, p. 291 (26-28)]. See [Guilfoy, 2002, p. 146; Marenbon, 1997a,<br />

p. 205, note 8].<br />

38 See note 25 above.<br />

39 Sanus is contrasted with cassus, “empty” [Nuchelmans, 1973, p. 144].<br />

40 Nuchelmans translates dispositiones animi as “mental attitudes” and notes that Abelard<br />

uses <strong>the</strong> similar phrase affectus animi to denote <strong>the</strong> moods <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb [Nuchelmans, 1973, p.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!