22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

462 Catarina Dutilh Novaes<br />

account <strong>the</strong> whole propositional context, and not only <strong>the</strong> syncategorematic term<br />

immediately preceding a given term. For this reason, <strong>the</strong> occurrence <strong>of</strong> several<br />

syncategorematic terms all having <strong>the</strong> same categorematic terms under <strong>the</strong>ir scope<br />

posed <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> those embedded syncategorematic terms over<br />

each o<strong>the</strong>r with respect to <strong>the</strong> (personal 29 ) supposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> categorematic terms<br />

in question.<br />

In particular, <strong>the</strong> treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation requires a great deal <strong>of</strong> ingenuity.<br />

The basic problem is: what is <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> a negating term over <strong>the</strong> supposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> a term which, if <strong>the</strong> negating term was removed, would have such-and-such<br />

personal supposition in a given proposition? In o<strong>the</strong>r words, rules determining<br />

<strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> supposition that a term would have if a negation is added to <strong>the</strong><br />

proposition where it stands are required for all three cases, namely if <strong>the</strong> term<br />

in <strong>the</strong> original proposition had determinate, confused and distributive or merely<br />

confused supposition. And this is where <strong>the</strong> issue arises.<br />

Buridan, for example, <strong>of</strong>fers an explicit rule concerning <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation<br />

over a term that, without <strong>the</strong> negation, would have determinate or merely confused<br />

supposition: A negating negation distributes every common term following it that<br />

without it would not be distributive and does not distribute anything that precedes<br />

it. [Buridan, 2001, 269]<br />

That means that, if in a proposition P, atermA has determinate supposition,<br />

and if a negation is added to P (yielding P ∗ )insuchawaythatA follows <strong>the</strong><br />

negation (immediate or mediately), <strong>the</strong>n A will have confused and distributive<br />

supposition. For <strong>the</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> clarity in <strong>the</strong> exposition, let me introduce a few<br />

notations in order to express this rule more precisely:<br />

Det(A)P ⇔ The term A has determinate supposition in proposition P .<br />

Dist(A)P ⇔ The term A has confused and distributive supposition in<br />

proposition P .<br />

Conf(A)P ⇔ The term A has merely confused supposition in proposition<br />

P .<br />

〈∼,A〉P ⇔ The negation is followed by term A in proposition P .<br />

Buridan’s rule can <strong>the</strong>n be formulated as follows:<br />

Rule 1 Det(A)P &〈∼,A〉P∗ → Dist(A)P ∗<br />

Rule 2 Conf(A)P &〈∼,A〉P∗ → Dist(A)P ∗<br />

There is, however, a serious problem concerning <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> a negating sign upon a<br />

term that, without <strong>the</strong> negation, would have confused and distributive supposition.<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory, it seems at first sight impossible to provide a<br />

general rule for <strong>the</strong> negation and for confused and distributive supposition, for <strong>the</strong><br />

following reason. Consider <strong>the</strong> four traditional kinds <strong>of</strong> categorical propositions:<br />

29 Or material supposition, if one follows Marsilius <strong>of</strong> Inghen in applying <strong>the</strong> traditional modes<br />

<strong>of</strong> personal supposition also to material supposition.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!