22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 439<br />

nians excelled not only in logic; <strong>the</strong>ir works on natural philosophy were probably<br />

even more influential; <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>of</strong>ten viewed as precursors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

turn’ in physics to take place a few centuries later (see [Sylla, 1982, 541]).<br />

The main authors among <strong>the</strong> Mertonians <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 14 th century (for<br />

our present purposes) are: Thomas Bradwardine, William Heytesbury, Richard<br />

Billingham, Roger Swyneshed (not to be confounded with <strong>the</strong> famous Richard<br />

Swyneshed, also a Mertonian and in fact known as ‘The Calculator’), and Richard<br />

Kilvington (for a more detailed presentation <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se authors, see [Ashworth<br />

and Spade, 1992]).<br />

Until not so long ago, it was though that Thomas Bradwardine’s contribution<br />

to logic was, to say <strong>the</strong> least, meager, and that his main contributions were to<br />

be found in <strong>the</strong> field <strong>of</strong> natural philosophy, ma<strong>the</strong>matics and <strong>the</strong>ology. But a<br />

recent interest in Bradwardine’s insolubilia (including a new edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> text<br />

now in preparation by Stephen Read) has arisen, showing that his work on Liarlike<br />

paradoxes was extremely innovative and sophisticated (cf. [Read, 2006b]).<br />

Since I will not be dealing with insolubilia in this chapter (as <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> topic<br />

<strong>of</strong> a different chapter in this volume), Bradwardine will not figure prominently in<br />

<strong>the</strong> analyses to follow. But his historical as well as philosophical importance must<br />

not be overlooked.<br />

William Heytesbury was seemingly more prolific than Bradwardine. The list<br />

<strong>of</strong> his still extant works is ra<strong>the</strong>r long, and includes treatises on consequence and<br />

obligations (which are only to be found in manuscripts — cf. [Longeway, 2003,<br />

section 2]), an influential treatise on divided and composite senses, some work on<br />

insolubilia, among o<strong>the</strong>rs. But he is most famous for his Regulae solvendi sophismata<br />

(1335) 10 , a work composed <strong>of</strong> six parts, where logical, semantic and physical<br />

sophisms are dealt with. In <strong>the</strong> first part he deals with <strong>the</strong> paradoxical propositions<br />

known as insolubilia, and his approach to <strong>the</strong>m was later to be influential,<br />

especially in <strong>the</strong> continent (e.g. Peter <strong>of</strong> Ailly’s treatment <strong>of</strong> insolubilia). The second<br />

part is dedicated to what we now call ‘reference in opaque contexts’; <strong>the</strong> third<br />

and fourth parts deal with semantic puzzles (related to <strong>the</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> relative<br />

pronouns, in <strong>the</strong> third, and to <strong>the</strong> terms ‘begins’ and ‘ceases’ in <strong>the</strong> fourth); <strong>the</strong><br />

last two concern physical puzzles. Thus, since <strong>the</strong> subject-matter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first two<br />

parts is to be dealt with elsewhere in this volume, and since <strong>the</strong> last two parts do<br />

not concern logic and/or semantics directly, in <strong>the</strong> analysis to follow Heytesbury<br />

will not figure prominently. Never<strong>the</strong>less, it is important to notice that Heytesbury<br />

was to become very influential in Italy in <strong>the</strong> 15 th century (while almost entirely<br />

forgotten in England), again exemplifying <strong>the</strong> exportation <strong>of</strong> British logic to Italy<br />

in <strong>the</strong> 14 th and 15 th centuries (see [Braakhuis, 1982]).<br />

Richard Billingham, ano<strong>the</strong>r influential Mertonian (apparently a few years younger<br />

than Bradwardine and Heytesbury), was most known in his own time for one <strong>of</strong> his<br />

works, his Speculum puerorum [Maierú, 1970; de Rijk, 1975; 1982], even though he<br />

also wrote on all <strong>the</strong> traditional topics in 14 th century logic (obligations — also in-<br />

10 A transcription <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> text by F. Pironet, en route for a critical edition, can be found at<br />

http://mapageweb.umontreal.ca/pironetf/Sophismata.html

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!