22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 549<br />

3 LATER MEDIAEVAL DEVELOPMENTS<br />

3.1 Modalities in Philosophy and Theology<br />

It has been assumed that <strong>the</strong> increasing interest in modal syllogistic and modal<br />

logic in general in early fourteenth century was associated with certain philosophical<br />

and <strong>the</strong>ological developments which added to <strong>the</strong> interest in modal <strong>the</strong>ories.<br />

These <strong>of</strong>ten involved <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> simultaneous alternatives which did not play a<br />

significant role in mid-thirteenth-century essentialist <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

Following <strong>the</strong> twelfth-century model, Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent (d. 1293) applied obligations<br />

logic to Trinitarian doctrine by assuming doctrinally impossible positions in<br />

order to see what followed from <strong>the</strong>m and what did not. 161 This was an influential<br />

idea. Several early fourteenth-century authors found an obligational analysis as<br />

a useful tool for analysing conceptual connections between <strong>the</strong>ological concepts.<br />

The most popular version <strong>of</strong> this logic was called positio. It deals with how an<br />

increasing set <strong>of</strong> true and false propositions might remain coherent in a disputation<br />

in which an opponent puts forward a contingent and false initial proposition and<br />

a respondent accepts this and accepts or denies o<strong>the</strong>r propositions in a logically<br />

consistent way. Irrelevant propositions are granted, denied or doubted according<br />

to <strong>the</strong> best knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> respondent. Relevant propositions should be treated<br />

in a consistent way. These ei<strong>the</strong>r follow from <strong>the</strong> initial position and/or what has<br />

been granted and/or <strong>the</strong> opposites <strong>of</strong> what has been correctly denied or are incompatible<br />

with <strong>the</strong>m. Thirteenth-century positio rules denied that a now false but<br />

possible position could refer to <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> an actual obligations discussion. This<br />

was in agreement with <strong>the</strong> traditional doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present. 162<br />

As part <strong>of</strong> his new interpretation <strong>of</strong> modal concepts, John Duns Scotus dropped<br />

this rule, a revision which made it possible to understand obligational answers as<br />

partial descriptions <strong>of</strong> how things could be instead <strong>of</strong> regarding <strong>the</strong>m as a internally<br />

consistent set <strong>of</strong> propositions without a sensible interpretation. 163<br />

Scotus’s revision <strong>of</strong> obligations rules was in agreement with his modal meta-<br />

161 Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent, Summae quaestionum ordinarium I.56 (Paris 1520, reprinted St. Bonaventure,<br />

N.Y.: The Franciscan Institute; Louvain: Nauwelaerts; Padenborn: Schöningh, 1953),<br />

vol. 2, 92r-v. One twelfth-century predecessor is Tractatus Emmeranus de impossibili positione,<br />

edited by L.M. de Rijk in ‘Some Thirteenth Century Tracts on <strong>the</strong> Game <strong>of</strong> Obligation’, Vivarium<br />

12 (1974), 94-123; an English translation by M. Yrjönsuuri in M. Yrjönsuuri (ed.), Medieval<br />

Formal <strong>Logic</strong>, The New Syn<strong>the</strong>se Historical Library 49 (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 217-23.<br />

162 See note 104 above.<br />

163 For Scotus’ revision, see Lectura I.39.1-5, 56, 59 in in Opera omnia, ed. C. Balić et al.<br />

(Vatican Ciry: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1950-), vol. 17; an English translation in John Duns<br />

Scotus, Contingency and Freedom: Lectura I.39, introduction, translation and commentary by<br />

A. Vos Jaczn., H. Veldhuis, A.H. Looman-Graaskamp, E. Dekker and N.W. den Bok, The New<br />

Syn<strong>the</strong>se Historical Library 42 (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994). For obligations<br />

logic, see M. Yrjönsuuri, Obligationes: 14 th Century <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong> Disputational Duties, Acta<br />

Philosophica Fennica 55 (Helsinki: Societas Philosophica Fennica, 1994) and note 83 above; for<br />

obligations logic in fourteenth-century <strong>the</strong>ology, see H. Gelber, It Could Have Been O<strong>the</strong>rwise.<br />

Contingency and Necessity in Dominican Theology at Oxford 1300-350, Studien und Texte zur<br />

Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 81 (Leiden: Brill, 2004).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!