22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

140 Ian Wilks<br />

catalogue <strong>of</strong> such patterns, presumed to be comprehensive. The treatment <strong>of</strong> this<br />

material is — like <strong>the</strong> treatment <strong>of</strong> argument forms in modal and tense logic —<br />

taxonomic ra<strong>the</strong>r than axiomatic. The intent is a list, not a reduction to principles.<br />

The discussion <strong>of</strong> deductive patterns arising from <strong>the</strong> conditional is, naturally,<br />

focused on reasoning “through <strong>the</strong> positing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent” and “through <strong>the</strong><br />

destruction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequent”: modus ponens and modus tollens respectively.<br />

These rules end up being variously specified, according to <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

conditional under question.<br />

Abelard starts with <strong>the</strong> four simple conditional forms: “If it is A it is B”; “If it<br />

is A it is not B”; “If it is not A it is B” and “If it is not A it is not B” [Abelard,<br />

1970, p. 498 (27–30)]. 107 From <strong>the</strong>se are generated eight moods <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogism, four arising from modus ponens, four from modus tollens [Abelard,<br />

1970, pp. 501 (30)–505 (7)]. The first mood applies “It is A” to“If it is A it is B.”<br />

The second applies “It is A” to“IfitisA it is not B.” The third applies “It is<br />

not A” to “If it is not A it is B.” The fourth applies “It is not A” to “If it is not<br />

A it is not B.” The fifth to eighth proceed in parallel fashion to apply <strong>the</strong> denial<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequent to each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> four forms. One notices <strong>the</strong> inefficiency <strong>of</strong> this<br />

presentation, since <strong>the</strong>re are, after all, really only two rules at work. The moods<br />

strike one as overly specified.<br />

But some need to make modus ponens and modus tollens case-specific emerges<br />

when Abelard considers <strong>the</strong> compound conditional forms [Abelard, 1970, p. 505<br />

(9)–516 (14)]. Compound conditionals involve nesting a conditional, ei<strong>the</strong>r in<br />

<strong>the</strong> consequent, or in <strong>the</strong> antecedent, or both. As we have seen, for Abelard<br />

nested conditionals <strong>the</strong>mselves involve a second kind <strong>of</strong> conditionality — that <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> temporal conditional. The rules <strong>of</strong> modus ponens and modus tollens are not<br />

quite enough to capture <strong>the</strong> truth conditions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se compounds, and need to be<br />

adapted to accommodate <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> two kinds <strong>of</strong> conditional relation. So a<br />

compound like “If it is A, <strong>the</strong>n when it is B it is C” falls under this version <strong>of</strong><br />

modus ponens: “When <strong>the</strong> antecedent is posited, its consequences will be at <strong>the</strong><br />

same time” [Abelard, 1970, p. 506 (4–5)]. A compound like “If, when it is A, it<br />

is B, <strong>the</strong>n it is C” falls under a different version: “When <strong>the</strong> antecedent exists<br />

with whatever is posited, any consequent <strong>of</strong> it is posited” [Abelard, 1970, p. 509<br />

(8–9)]. Compound conditionals with temporal qualification in both antecedent<br />

and consequent will need ano<strong>the</strong>r version again.<br />

Abelard accordingly tailors modus ponens and modus tollens to handle different<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> content. This is an impediment to recognizing <strong>the</strong> merits <strong>of</strong> a very<br />

different approach: keep <strong>the</strong> rules <strong>the</strong> same for all cases and develop a more sophisticated<br />

account <strong>of</strong> propositional substitution. For all his innovations at a more<br />

foundational level <strong>of</strong> propositional logic, Abelard is evidently not ready to take this<br />

step.<br />

The final tally <strong>of</strong> moods for <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogism gives us one hundred and<br />

twenty-eight. These include two fur<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> case. (i) Besides <strong>the</strong> simple and<br />

107 The variables “A” and“B” are present in Abelard, and are derived from Boethius. (Upper<br />

case forms are used here, not <strong>the</strong> lower case forms in <strong>the</strong> text, for typographical clarity.)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!