22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 241<br />

If a term has distributive supposition in a proposition, <strong>the</strong>n if you<br />

change its quantifier sign so as to give it determinate supposition (inserting<br />

a negation after <strong>the</strong> denoting phrase containing <strong>the</strong> term if it<br />

changes from affirmative to negative, or vice versa) <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> resulting<br />

proposition is entailed by <strong>the</strong> original.<br />

If a term has determinate supposition in a proposition, <strong>the</strong>n if you<br />

change its quantifier sign so as to give it merely confused supposition<br />

(inserting a negation after <strong>the</strong> denoting phrase containing <strong>the</strong> term if it<br />

changes from affirmative to negative, or vice versa) <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> resulting<br />

proposition is entailed by <strong>the</strong> original. 97<br />

The ideas behind <strong>the</strong>se rules are neat, but a great deal <strong>of</strong> work remains to be done.<br />

When it was done it was within a somewhat different framework — roughly that<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> next section.<br />

8 MODES OF SUPPOSITION: THE LATER VIEW<br />

8.1 The Fourteenth Century Definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Modes<br />

In <strong>the</strong> 14 th century, Walter Burley, William Ockham, and John Buridan developed<br />

a new approach to <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> common personal supposition. It<br />

is not clear whe<strong>the</strong>r, or how, <strong>the</strong>y saw <strong>the</strong>ir accounts as being different from those<br />

given by earlier authors, but <strong>the</strong> accounts did differ in three important ways. (1)<br />

The modes are defined in terms <strong>of</strong> valid inferences, not in terms <strong>of</strong> quantities such<br />

as ‘many’ or ‘any’. (2) The modes <strong>of</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> terms are defined globally<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> locally, so that embedding a proposition in a larger one can alter not<br />

just mobility but also mode <strong>of</strong> supposition. (3) In earlier accounts some good<br />

inferences depend on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> term in question has or lacks mobility, but rules<br />

for <strong>the</strong>se inferences are phrased in terms not <strong>of</strong> mobility but in terms <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition. When a term has distributive but immobile supposition, rules based<br />

on distributivity tend to fail. Conversely, a term without distributive supposition<br />

might have <strong>the</strong> mobility needed to yield an inference that <strong>the</strong> rules deny to terms<br />

that are not distributive. In <strong>the</strong> later <strong>the</strong>ory, as a result <strong>of</strong> (1) and (2) <strong>the</strong> modes<br />

<strong>of</strong> supposition are brought into conformity with kinds <strong>of</strong> mobility.<br />

The new accounts define <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> a term in a proposition 98<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> conditions on ascent and descent under that term in <strong>the</strong> proposition.<br />

(A descent is similar to a quantifier instantiation step in modern logic; an ascent<br />

97 When <strong>the</strong> only quantifier signs are ‘some’, ‘every’ and’no’, it is not possible to give an<br />

example <strong>of</strong> this second rule. The possibility <strong>of</strong> giving such an example arises in some postmedieval<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories; see Ashworth 1974 IV.II.1 on special invented signs governing supposition.<br />

98 Some authors held that only main terms have personal supposition in a proposition (where<br />

a main term is one that is not part <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r term). Burley DS para 5-15 argues this. But <strong>the</strong><br />

definitions to be given <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> supposition apply meaningfully to any term in a proposition.<br />

In practice, authors sometimes applied <strong>the</strong> definitions to parts <strong>of</strong> terms, even when denying that<br />

this is possible.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!