22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 455<br />

differs from every man’. According to Maulevelt, <strong>the</strong> descent allowed for <strong>the</strong> term<br />

‘man’ giving <strong>the</strong> intended meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition is ‘Socrates differs from this<br />

man and that man and. . . ’, and not ‘Socrates differs from this man or that man<br />

or...’ (although in principle, <strong>the</strong> second descent should also be allowed, since<br />

nominal conjunction should imply <strong>the</strong> corresponding nominal disjunction). In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, according to Maulevelt, nominal conjunctive descent is not only a<br />

logical possibility; it is also <strong>the</strong> actual descent required by some real cases.<br />

Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony, writing after Maulevelt, explicitly rejects his analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

‘Socrates differs from every man’ as requiring nominal conjunctive descent; according<br />

to him, ‘man’ in this case should have determinate and not merely confused<br />

supposition (cf. [Read, 1991b, 80]). Moreover, Albert criticizes <strong>the</strong> inclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> clause for nominal conjunctive descent in <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> merely confused<br />

supposition, thus implicitly defending <strong>the</strong> idea that nominal conjunctive descent is<br />

not a phenomenon that needs to be taken into account in <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong><br />

personal supposition (being at best only a logical possibility). Obviously, for those<br />

who reject nominal conjunctive descent as a relevant phenomenon, such as Albert<br />

<strong>of</strong> Saxony, three modes <strong>of</strong> personal supposition provide a complete picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

(personal) supposition <strong>of</strong> all terms not only in <strong>the</strong> sense that all cases were taken<br />

into account (which happens anyway if merely confused supposition is defined as<br />

a catch-all clause), but also in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>se three categories are sufficiently<br />

fine-grained and discriminating so as to give a coherent grouping <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se semantic<br />

phenomena, since <strong>the</strong>y correspond to <strong>the</strong> three relevant kinds <strong>of</strong> descent.<br />

Among those who recognize nominal conjunctive descent as an important phenomenon,<br />

two positions are possible; ei<strong>the</strong>r to associate nominal conjunctive descent<br />

to merely confused supposition, toge<strong>the</strong>r with nominal disjunctive descent<br />

(as did Maulevelt and later Paul <strong>of</strong> Venice — cf. [Read, 1991a, 53]), yielding thus<br />

a ra<strong>the</strong>r heterogeneous notion <strong>of</strong> merely confused supposition as a ‘miscellaneous’<br />

category; or to associate nominal conjunctive descent to a fourth mode <strong>of</strong> personal<br />

supposition altoge<strong>the</strong>r. According to our current state <strong>of</strong> knowledge, while<br />

<strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> a descensus copulatim (nominal conjunctive supposition) seems to<br />

have been familiar in Paris and Oxford in <strong>the</strong> 1350s and 1360s, <strong>the</strong> first to associate<br />

a fourth mode <strong>of</strong> supposition to nominal conjunctive descent seems to have<br />

been Thomas <strong>of</strong> Cleves (cf. [Read, 1991a; 1991b]) in his Suppositiones written in<br />

<strong>the</strong> first half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1370s in Paris 23 , before he moved on to be <strong>the</strong> rector <strong>of</strong> St.<br />

Stephen’s ca<strong>the</strong>dral school in Vienna This fourth mode <strong>of</strong> personal supposition<br />

became known as collective supposition.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> examples usually associated with nominal conjunctive descent (from<br />

[Read, 1991a]) were: ‘You are not every man’, ‘No animal is every man’, and ‘Some<br />

penny will be seen by every man’ (in all three cases with respect to ‘man’). But<br />

in such cases, <strong>the</strong> opponents <strong>of</strong> descensus copulatim usually proceeded by showing<br />

that, if this kind <strong>of</strong> descent was possible at all, so were o<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> descent,<br />

23 At this point, no surviving manuscript <strong>of</strong> Thomas <strong>of</strong> Cleves’ Suppositiones has been located;<br />

but a reconstruction <strong>of</strong> it has been made recently (in [Bos, 2004]) on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> references made<br />

to this work in o<strong>the</strong>r texts.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!