22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Logic</strong> and Theories <strong>of</strong> Meaning . . . 383<br />

object known and <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> knowing (habitudo rei intellectae ad actum intelligendi).<br />

Second intentions are always rationate entities, because concrete second<br />

intentions are things that are secondarily known, and abstract second intentions<br />

are relations between <strong>the</strong> objects known and <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> knowing (18).<br />

According to Hervaeus, first as well as second intentions, whe<strong>the</strong>r concrete or<br />

abstract, exist obiective (i.e. as objective contents) in <strong>the</strong> intellect (17), since<br />

everything that is known exists as an object in <strong>the</strong> intellect. Thus, when <strong>the</strong><br />

intellect knows a man or a horse, man or horse is said to exist objectively in<br />

<strong>the</strong> intellect as first concrete intentions. Second intentions are founded upon first<br />

intentions and <strong>the</strong>refore, <strong>the</strong>y exist objectively in <strong>the</strong> intellect as well (23).<br />

Intentionality exists on two levels, according to Hervaeus. 182 First concrete<br />

intentions are founded upon <strong>the</strong> objects intellected that possess real being outside<br />

<strong>the</strong> mind. The intentionality itself, i.e. <strong>the</strong> relationship between object intellected<br />

and <strong>the</strong> intellect, is a first abstract intention or primary intentionality. If this<br />

primary intentionality is itself <strong>the</strong> object intellected, it is <strong>the</strong> foundation <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

relationship to <strong>the</strong> intellect: a secondary intentionality. In this case <strong>the</strong> first<br />

abstract intention is at <strong>the</strong> same time a second concrete intention. 183 So, ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

mediately or immediately, all second intentions are founded upon a first one, which<br />

in its turn is founded upon extra mental reality.<br />

Hervaeus deviates from Radulphus on several points. I mention <strong>the</strong> most important<br />

ones:<br />

1. A first intention is not identical with <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> intellection. This is only<br />

<strong>the</strong> case from <strong>the</strong> viewpoint <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellect, which is not <strong>of</strong> interest for <strong>the</strong><br />

logician.<br />

2. A concrete first intention is not an extra mental object taken absolutely, but<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r that object as known by <strong>the</strong> intellect.<br />

3. First and second intentions are not founded upon different modes <strong>of</strong> being<br />

(properties) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object known. First intentions have <strong>the</strong>ir foundation in<br />

reality, and second intentions are founded upon first intentions.<br />

4. All intentions exist objectively in <strong>the</strong> intellect.<br />

Thus, like Radulphus, Hervaeus turns out to be aware that our intellect makes<br />

distinctions that are ultimately founded upon reality, but, unlike Radulphus, he<br />

does not think that every abstract intention corresponds with a (common) mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> being in reality.<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> French Franciscan Peter Aureol (working in Paris ca. 1320) was a<br />

<strong>the</strong>ologian and not a logician, he never<strong>the</strong>less deserves a place in <strong>the</strong>se paragraphs<br />

on <strong>the</strong> intentionality debate, because he opposed <strong>the</strong> views <strong>of</strong> Radulphus Brito<br />

and Hervaeus Natalis and is primarily known as one <strong>of</strong> Ockham’s forerunners as<br />

a conceptualist, although recent studies have shown his originality and historical<br />

182 De secundis intentionibus, dist. III, q. 3c, quoted by De Rijk [2005, p. 282].<br />

183 De Rijk [2005, p. 280].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!