22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

74 John Marenbon<br />

<strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se disputations I forced him through <strong>the</strong> most clearly<br />

reasoned arguments to change his old view about universals, indeed to<br />

reject it. He held <strong>the</strong> view about <strong>the</strong> commonness <strong>of</strong> universals according<br />

to which <strong>the</strong> same thing as a thing (essentialiter) isatoneand<strong>the</strong><br />

same time whole within its single individuals, which do not differ as<br />

things (in essentia) but only through <strong>the</strong> variety <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir many accidents.<br />

He corrected his view by saying from <strong>the</strong>n on that <strong>the</strong> thing is<br />

<strong>the</strong> same, not as a thing, but through non-difference (non essentialiter<br />

sed indifferenter). And, since for logicians <strong>the</strong> chief question about<br />

universals has always been in this — so much so that even Porphyry,<br />

writing about universals in his Isagoge, does not presume to give a<br />

conclusion, saying ‘To treat <strong>of</strong> this is extremely pr<strong>of</strong>ound’ — when<br />

William had no choice but to correct, or ra<strong>the</strong>r abandon, this view, his<br />

lectures came to be so badly regarded that <strong>the</strong>y were hardly accepted<br />

on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r parts <strong>of</strong> logic, as if <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> this art were contained<br />

in that one view, on universals.[Peter Abelard, 1967, 65:80 – 66:100]<br />

The first view held by William is usually labelled ‘Material Essence Realism’; a<br />

fuller account <strong>of</strong> it, along with his own counter-arguments, can be found in both<br />

<strong>of</strong> Abelard’s mature Porphyry commentaries (from c. 1119, and c. 1125). But<br />

Abelard may not have developed by 1108 <strong>the</strong> same arguments that he would later<br />

use. Nor is it clear whe<strong>the</strong>r Material Essence Realism was William’s invention,<br />

or merely <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory he happened to have adopted. Moreover, Abelard wrote<br />

his Story <strong>of</strong> my Disasters probably c. 1131, nearly a quarter <strong>of</strong> a century after<br />

this dispute with William, and with <strong>the</strong> aim <strong>of</strong> preparing for his re-entry into <strong>the</strong><br />

Parisian schools by casting his controversial career and personal life in a favourable<br />

light, under which he was <strong>the</strong> victim <strong>of</strong> envy. It would not be surprising if he<br />

had magnified <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> his difference with William or <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>of</strong> his<br />

intellectual victory.<br />

There are also chronicle sources which provide some names and suggestions<br />

about logic in <strong>the</strong> late eleventh century. In Hermann <strong>of</strong> Tournai’s account (written<br />

1142 or later) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> restoration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> abbey at Tournai by Odo (who would<br />

go on to write On Original Sin), he describes a certain master Rainbertus <strong>of</strong> Lille<br />

as reading logic ‘in <strong>the</strong> same way as certain contemporaries in voce’ [Hermann <strong>of</strong><br />

Tournai, 1883, 275]. He contrasts Rainbertus unfavourably with Odo, who ‘read<br />

logic for his pupils in re in <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>of</strong> Boethius and <strong>the</strong> ancient doctors’ (...<br />

eandem dialecticam non iuxta quosdam modernos in voce, sed more Boetii antiquorum<br />

doctorum in re discipulis legebat). Hermann goes on to apply to logicians like<br />

Rainbertus a comment that Anselm addresses to Roscelin (in <strong>the</strong> revised version<br />

<strong>of</strong> his treatise), that <strong>the</strong>y are not ‘dialecticians, but heretics in dialectic’ [Hermann<br />

<strong>of</strong> Tournai, 1883, 275]. A chronicle from Fleury (c. 1110) records that at <strong>the</strong> time<br />

when Lanfranc died, that is to say, 1087, <strong>the</strong> eminent logicians were John, who argued<br />

that <strong>the</strong> art <strong>of</strong> logic is ‘concerned with utterances’ (vocalis), and his followers,<br />

Robert <strong>of</strong> Paris, Roscelin <strong>of</strong> Compiègne and Arnulf <strong>of</strong> Laon [Bouquet, 1781, 3]. Of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se names, Roscelin is well known through Anselm’s testimony, and it may be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!