22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

142 Ian Wilks<br />

itself. The relationships between connectives can be very perspicuously expressed<br />

by starting with a material account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditional. But this material account<br />

is so counter-intuitive that it is not a natural starting point at all. A natural<br />

starting point is some kind <strong>of</strong> relevance account, but on this <strong>the</strong> relationships<br />

between connectives are much easier to mis-state and mis-construe.<br />

Philosophers sometimes refer to very basic propositional logic, ra<strong>the</strong>r archly,<br />

as “baby logic.” Well, it took philosophers about as long to develop a working<br />

account <strong>of</strong> baby logic as it took physicists to develop a working account <strong>of</strong> relativity<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory. The written product <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s intense labours in <strong>the</strong> former area are<br />

helpful in showing us why this was so.<br />

PART 3: ABELARD’S CONTEMPORARIES<br />

Among Abelard’s contemporaries, and in <strong>the</strong> immediate aftermath <strong>of</strong> his career,<br />

no o<strong>the</strong>r figure emerges as having anything like his stature and influence within<br />

<strong>the</strong> field <strong>of</strong> logic. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand he did have rivals during his life, and <strong>the</strong>y,<br />

like he, established schools to continue <strong>the</strong> rivalry.<br />

Among his rivals four names in particular emerge: Adam <strong>of</strong> Balsham, Alberic<br />

<strong>of</strong> Paris, Gilbert <strong>of</strong> Poitiers and Robert <strong>of</strong> Melun. These were all younger contemporaries,<br />

whose teaching careers were all launched before Abelard’s was ended.<br />

According to current scholarly consensus, <strong>the</strong>ir adherents were, respectively, known<br />

as <strong>the</strong> Parvipontani (or Adamitae), <strong>the</strong> Montani (or Albricani), <strong>the</strong> Porretani (or<br />

Gilebertini) and <strong>the</strong> Melidunenses (or Robertini) [Iwakuma and Ebbesen, 1992, p.<br />

174]. The adherents <strong>of</strong> Abelard were <strong>the</strong> Nominales. Gilbert is <strong>of</strong> course famous<br />

in his own right as a philosopher and <strong>the</strong>ologian, and cuts a substantial figure in<br />

<strong>the</strong> twelfth century independently <strong>of</strong> his work in logic. Alberic and Robert, by<br />

contrast, are best known through <strong>the</strong> literary products <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir schools. The most<br />

notable logical text to emerge from any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schools <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s rivals is <strong>the</strong> Ars<br />

Meliduna, a large work which provides a rich and varied conspectus <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> views<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Melidunenses; it has been described as “<strong>the</strong> climactic achievement <strong>of</strong> logic<br />

in <strong>the</strong> second half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> twelfth century” [Jacobi, 1988, p. 245].<br />

The above school classification represents <strong>the</strong> received scholarly view on <strong>the</strong><br />

matter. It is <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> extensive efforts over <strong>the</strong> past decades in assembling<br />

<strong>the</strong> scattered and <strong>of</strong>ten fragmentary literary remains <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schools. Some ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

basic questions have arisen, such as whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> Montani were in fact <strong>the</strong> same<br />

as <strong>the</strong> Albricani, and whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> Nominales were in fact <strong>the</strong> followers <strong>of</strong> Abelard<br />

[Iwakuma and Ebbesen, 1992, p. 174]. That points as fundamental as <strong>the</strong>se have<br />

been under relatively recent discussion shows how incipient our knowledge <strong>of</strong> this<br />

era in <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> logic is.<br />

The textual evidence ranges from treatises and fragments <strong>of</strong> treatises to passing<br />

references made by non-philosophical authors. The treatises <strong>the</strong>mselves pose<br />

substantial interpretative problems, having been composed both by and for those<br />

immersed in <strong>the</strong> technical controversies <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> day. They demand a knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> context which <strong>the</strong>y do little to provide. A school <strong>the</strong>orem is <strong>of</strong>ten presented

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!