22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Nominalist Semantics <strong>of</strong> Ockham and Buridan 411<br />

on Ockham’s ontological program. 42 According to “<strong>the</strong> received view”, 43 Ockham’s<br />

primitive vocabulary would contain only syncategorematic terms (roughly,<br />

logical connectives) and absolute terms, i.e., terms subordinated to absolute concepts,<br />

whereby individuals are conceived absolutely (though in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> universal<br />

concepts, indifferently), not in relation to anything else. Accordingly, on<br />

this view, Ockham is committed to holding that all connotative terms (i.e., terms<br />

subordinated to connotative concepts whereby we conceive <strong>of</strong> individuals in relation<br />

to o<strong>the</strong>r things, <strong>the</strong> connotata <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term) are semantically compositional;<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir semantic values are functionally determined by <strong>the</strong> semantic values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

components <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir nominal definitions. Equivalently, <strong>the</strong> view holds that all<br />

connotative concepts are complex, i.e., <strong>the</strong>re are no simple connotative concepts.<br />

The rationale for <strong>the</strong> view is Ockham’s repeated claim that all connotative terms<br />

have nominal definitions, which coupled with <strong>the</strong> idea that nominal definitions are<br />

synonymous with <strong>the</strong>ir definita because <strong>the</strong>y are subordinated to <strong>the</strong> same concept,<br />

directly yields <strong>the</strong> above <strong>the</strong>ses. Panaccio’s meticulous analysis <strong>of</strong> Ockham’s<br />

texts, however, cast serious doubt on <strong>the</strong> assumption that nominal definitions for<br />

Ockham always have to be strictly synonymous with <strong>the</strong>ir definita on account <strong>of</strong><br />

being subordinated to <strong>the</strong> same concept, and, correspondingly, that <strong>the</strong>re are no<br />

simple connotative concepts for Ockham.<br />

But even without trying to settle this issue <strong>of</strong> Ockham scholarship, one can note<br />

that what is problematic with a severely limited primitive vocabulary is <strong>the</strong> feasibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> providing plausible analyses in all cases when needed. However, <strong>the</strong> primitive<br />

vocabulary may be enhanced not only by means <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> addition <strong>of</strong> primitive<br />

connotative terms (ones subordinated to simple connotative concepts), but also by<br />

means <strong>of</strong> enhancing <strong>the</strong> class <strong>of</strong> syncategoremata, and construe apparently primitive<br />

connotative terms as complexes <strong>of</strong> absolute terms and some “non-standard”<br />

syncategoremata. Take for instance <strong>the</strong> Latin phrase ‘hominis asinus’ (‘donkey<br />

<strong>of</strong> a man’). This is clearly a complex term, consisting <strong>of</strong> a simple absolute term<br />

‘asinus’ (‘donkey’) and an apparently simple connotative term, ‘hominis’ (‘<strong>of</strong> a<br />

man’), signifying things in relation to men as <strong>the</strong>ir possession. However, if we<br />

look at <strong>the</strong> corresponding English term, <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> simplicity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Latin connotative term ‘hominis’ is dissolved in <strong>the</strong> syntactical structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

phrase ‘<strong>of</strong> a man’, which seems to indicate that in <strong>the</strong> formation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept expressed<br />

both by ‘hominis’ and by ‘<strong>of</strong> a man’ actually several concepts are involved,<br />

42 See Panaccio, C. “Connotative Terms in Ockham’s Mental Language”, Cahiers<br />

d’épistémologie 9016(1990), pp. 1-22. For more recent treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue see Chalmers,<br />

D. “Is There Synonymy in Ockham’s Mental Language?” in The Cambridge Companion to Ockham,<br />

ed. P. V. Spade, Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1999, pp. 76-99; and Panaccio,<br />

C. “Semantics and Mental Language,” ibid., pp. 53-75. Panaccio’s most recent summary account<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> debate can be found in his Ockham on Concepts.<br />

43 Cf., e.g., Spade, P. V. “Ockham’s Distinctions between Absolute and Connotative Terms,”<br />

Vivarium 13 (1975), pp. 55–76; Spade, P. V. “Synonymy and Equivocation in Ockham’s Mental<br />

Language”, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong> Philosophy 18(1980), pp. 9-22. For Spade’s most recent<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue, see Spade, Paul Vincent, ”William <strong>of</strong> Ockham”, The Stanford Encyclopedia<br />

<strong>of</strong> Philosophy (Fall 2006 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/<br />

archives/fall2006/entries/ockham/

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!