22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

310 Henrik Lagerlund<br />

Kilwardby. Necessity per accidens belongs to all o<strong>the</strong>r necessity proposition that<br />

do not have <strong>the</strong> intrinsic relation between subject and predicate.<br />

He also stresses that in a per se necessity proposition, <strong>the</strong> subject must be ‘per se<br />

aliquod ipsius predicati’. He seems to mean that in such a proposition, <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

has <strong>the</strong> predicate as an essential property; in o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> subject has <strong>the</strong><br />

predicate as a necessary property through itself and not through something else.<br />

A syllogistic necessity proposition is <strong>the</strong>n understood as a proposition expressing<br />

essential properties <strong>of</strong> things located in a genus-species structure. He seems to<br />

assume that in a necessity proposition per se, <strong>the</strong> subject term is not an accidental<br />

term, but an essential or a necessary term, and that <strong>the</strong> subject is essentially (per<br />

se), and not only through inseparability, linked to <strong>the</strong> predicate. Consequently, if<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject term is necessary and <strong>the</strong> link is necessary, it follows that <strong>the</strong> predicate<br />

term cannot be a contingent (accidental) term. It must be necessary as well.<br />

The Aristotelian <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> necessity syllogistic is thus limited to a special class<br />

<strong>of</strong> terms, which all stand for substances. The same terminology is also used to<br />

explain <strong>the</strong> syllogistic for contingency propositions, which means that Kilwardby<br />

is trying to develop a uniform and highly original interpretation. There are several<br />

contemporary scholars that have developed a similar interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aristotle. 68<br />

In interpreting Aristotle’s modal syllogistics, most medievals saw <strong>the</strong> need to<br />

introduce a distinction between different kinds <strong>of</strong> assertoric proposition. In <strong>the</strong><br />

mixed syllogism L–L, <strong>the</strong> assertoric minor premise cannot be any kind <strong>of</strong> assertoric<br />

sentence, since <strong>the</strong> terms could just be accidentally connected. Kilwardby<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore introduces a distinction between simply (simpliciter) and as <strong>of</strong> now (ut<br />

nunc) assertoric propositions. The seed <strong>of</strong> this distinction can already be found<br />

in Aristotle (Prior Analytics I, 15, 34b7-18), but Kilwardby <strong>of</strong> course uses his<br />

per se/per accidens distinction to spell out <strong>the</strong> difference. A simply assertoric<br />

proposition involves a per se predication while an as <strong>of</strong> now assertoric proposition<br />

involves a per accidens predication. In such a way he can ensure that an essential<br />

connection between <strong>the</strong> terms in <strong>the</strong> valid L–L syllogisms are preserved to<br />

<strong>the</strong> conclusion. This is not unproblematic, 69 but <strong>the</strong> distinction between different<br />

assertoric propositions needed somehow to be made and it remained a problem all<br />

<strong>the</strong> way through <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> end, however, Kilwardby does not quite succeed in getting just <strong>the</strong> moods<br />

accepted by Aristotle. He for example accepts –LL for <strong>the</strong> first figure, which is not<br />

accepted by Aristotle, and does not manage to get –CC and LCC for Disamis in<br />

<strong>the</strong> third figure. 70 There are also some o<strong>the</strong>r moods that he does not succeed in<br />

validating and some o<strong>the</strong>rs which he get but which are not accepted by Aristotle,<br />

but perhaps he gets as close as one possible can get to making Aristotle’s system<br />

consistent. 71<br />

68 [van Rijen, 1989; Patterson, 1995; Thom, 1996; Nortmann, 1996].<br />

69 See [Lagerlund, 2000, 39-42].<br />

70 For <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se names see below.<br />

71 See [Knuuttila, 1996; Lagerlund, 2000; Thom, 2004].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!