22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 239<br />

and <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> supposition — <strong>of</strong> ‘a man’; in <strong>the</strong> good example it has merely<br />

confused supposition, and in <strong>the</strong> bad one it has determinate supposition. So <strong>the</strong><br />

rule is formulated in terms <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r you move from many cases <strong>of</strong> determinate<br />

supposition to determinate supposition, or to merely confused supposition.<br />

Rule IV An argument from determinate supposition to distributive confused<br />

supposition does not follow, but only to merely confused supposition.<br />

Thus this does not follow: ‘a man is not seen by Socrates; <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

Socrates does not see a man’ — e.g. if Socrates sees one man only. But<br />

this follows correctly: ‘a man is seen by every man; <strong>the</strong>refore every man<br />

sees a man’. [Ibid] 95<br />

The badness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first inference and goodness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second are obvious; <strong>the</strong> rule<br />

identifies <strong>the</strong> difference in terms <strong>of</strong> a principle about modes <strong>of</strong> supposition.<br />

Rule V An argument from distributive confused supposition to determinate<br />

supposition does follow, but not from merely confused supposition.<br />

Thus this follows: ‘Socrates does not see a man; <strong>the</strong>refore a man is<br />

not seen by Socrates’. But this does not: ‘every man sees a man (e.g.,<br />

every man sees only himself); <strong>the</strong>refore a man is seen by every man’.<br />

[Ibid (119)]<br />

In <strong>the</strong> first inference ‘man’ goes from distributive supposition to determinate supposition,<br />

and in <strong>the</strong> second it goes from merely confused to determinate. The rule<br />

blames <strong>the</strong> goodness/badness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se inferences on <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modes <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition.<br />

These rules all seem to have insight behind <strong>the</strong>m, and <strong>the</strong>y look promising as<br />

part <strong>of</strong> an overall <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> inference in terms <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> supposition. But <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are some problems with <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Problem 1: Embedded propositions<br />

The rules are all illustrated by fairly simple categorical propositions, but <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

supposed to hold in general. However, <strong>the</strong> rules are stated in terms <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition, which do not change when a proposition is embedded in something<br />

more complex — yet <strong>the</strong> goodness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inferences can be affected by this. A<br />

simple example <strong>of</strong> an application <strong>of</strong> Rule IV is this inference:<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore,<br />

If a man is seen by every man, <strong>the</strong>n a man is seen by every man;<br />

If every man sees a man, <strong>the</strong>n a man is seen by every man.<br />

95The translation quoted here has been altered in conformity with discussion in <strong>the</strong> Preface to<br />

[Kretzmann, 1968].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!