22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Assimilation <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian and Arabic <strong>Logic</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> Later Thirteenth Century 305<br />

4.2 The De interpretatione<br />

The De interpretatione commentary <strong>of</strong> Kilwardby in <strong>the</strong> same series <strong>of</strong> lectures as<br />

mentioned above is also very interesting. Aristotle begins his work by saying that<br />

“spoken words are signs <strong>of</strong> mental affections and written words are signs <strong>of</strong> spoken<br />

words.” These lines were very influential and Kilwardby starts his commentary by<br />

expanding on <strong>the</strong>m. Thought are likenesses <strong>of</strong> reality, he claims, and he identifies<br />

<strong>the</strong> meaning (signification) <strong>of</strong> an utterance with <strong>the</strong> intelligible species (form) in<br />

<strong>the</strong> intellective soul. It is hence <strong>the</strong> form in singulars or <strong>the</strong> essence in reality that<br />

correspond to <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> words.<br />

In his comments on predication in <strong>the</strong> De interpretatione commentary, he explicitly<br />

compares predication, that is, <strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>the</strong> subject and <strong>the</strong><br />

predicate, with <strong>the</strong> relation between form and matter. He uses <strong>the</strong> terminology<br />

‘forma predicati’ or ‘<strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate’ to explicate how <strong>the</strong> predicate inheres<br />

in <strong>the</strong> subject. The proposition ‘Socrates in white’ is true because whiteness<br />

inheres in Socrates, and in <strong>the</strong> linguistic expression <strong>the</strong> ontological relation is mirrored.<br />

As <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> white informs a substance or matter <strong>the</strong> predicate informs<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject. The whiteness in Socrates is an accidental form, since he in only<br />

contingently white, so <strong>the</strong> predication expressing this truth is only an accidental<br />

predication, but supposedly in regards to essential or substantial forms <strong>the</strong> corresponding<br />

predication is essential or substantial, as in ‘A human being is rational’,<br />

since ‘rational’ is in this case a reference to <strong>the</strong> human soul. Kilwardby brings<br />

<strong>the</strong>se thoughts into his analysis <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s modal syllogistics as well (see <strong>the</strong><br />

discussion below).<br />

One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most interesting and also one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most discussed parts <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

De interpretatione is, <strong>of</strong> course, Chapter 9. Albert <strong>the</strong> Great’s and Thomas<br />

Aquinas’ treatments <strong>of</strong> this chapter in <strong>the</strong>ir respective commentaries are very similar<br />

and obviously influenced by Averroes discussion in his middle commentary<br />

on De interpretatione. 59 I will here present some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most interesting parts <strong>of</strong><br />

Aquinas’ discussion.<br />

In Lectio 13, Aquinas begins by dividing propositions (enuntiationes). The first<br />

division is according to unity, that is, into simple and conjunctive propositions;<br />

<strong>the</strong> second division is according to quantity, that is, into affirmative and negative<br />

propositions; <strong>the</strong> third division is into quality, that is, into universal, particular,<br />

indefinite and singular propositions. The forth division is according to time and<br />

<strong>the</strong>n propositions divide into propositions about <strong>the</strong> past, present and <strong>the</strong> future.<br />

The fifth and final division is in regards to matter. The matter <strong>of</strong> a proposition is<br />

taken from <strong>the</strong> relationship <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate to <strong>the</strong> subject. If <strong>the</strong> predicate is per<br />

se in <strong>the</strong> subject, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is said to be in necessary or natural matter.<br />

The examples he gives are ‘A human being is an animal’ and ‘A human being is<br />

risible’. The <strong>the</strong> first case <strong>the</strong> relation is a genus to a species and in <strong>the</strong> second it<br />

is a property (proprium) to a species. If <strong>the</strong> predicate is repugnant <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

as in ‘A human being is an ass’, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is in impossible or remote<br />

59 See [Knuuttila, 2006].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!