22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 121<br />

in both premises but must have a present tensed conclusion: “Every mortal will<br />

die; every mortal is a living thing; <strong>the</strong>refore some living thing will die” [Abelard,<br />

1970, p. 248 (26-28)]. 73<br />

While Abelard’s handling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> standard syllogisms is axiomatic in orientation,<br />

his handling <strong>of</strong> ones with modal and tense variation is taxonomic ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

axiomatic; he wishes simply to identify a few kinds <strong>of</strong> non-standard syllogism,<br />

not to systematize <strong>the</strong>m. And nowhere in his treatment <strong>of</strong> categorical syllogisms,<br />

standard or non-standard, does Abelard follow <strong>the</strong> deeper purposes <strong>of</strong> investigating<br />

<strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inferential link itself, and how propositions come to be so<br />

linked. This project is reserved for his treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogism,<br />

and can indeed be viewed as his chief objective <strong>the</strong>re.<br />

PART 2: ABELARD ON TOPICS, HYPOTHETICAL PROPOSITIONS AND<br />

HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS<br />

Just as categorical syllogisms are broached in <strong>the</strong> Dialectica only after prior<br />

ground-laying discussion, so with hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms. The ground-laying discussion<br />

for <strong>the</strong>se latter, indeed, constitutes <strong>the</strong> largest single section <strong>of</strong> that work.<br />

It is important to grasp <strong>the</strong> procedure Abelard has in mind. The predicative<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> terms within categorical syllogisms is what makes those syllogisms work,<br />

and so we gain insight into <strong>the</strong> working <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> syllogisms by means <strong>of</strong> insight into<br />

that predicative relation. But hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms have terms too; <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong><br />

antecedents and consequents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditionals contained in <strong>the</strong> syllogisms (or <strong>the</strong><br />

disjuncts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> corresponding disjunctions). These clause-length terms are in an<br />

implicative relation which needs to be studied as a preliminary for hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogisms, just as <strong>the</strong> predicative relation needs to be studied as a preliminary for<br />

categorical ones. Abelard attempts to meet this need, and in so doing gives an<br />

extended account <strong>of</strong> conditionals (and a corresponding account <strong>of</strong> disjunctions).<br />

This extended account is meant to establish a process for ascertaining when <strong>the</strong><br />

antecedents and consequents <strong>of</strong> conditionals actually do stand in an implicative<br />

relation. The key notion in this confirmatory process is <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topic.<br />

It is here that Abelard’s expository program takes what is, from a contemporary<br />

perspective, a very unfamiliar turn. Clearly one goes nowhere in this explanatory<br />

sequence without a good sense <strong>of</strong> what a topic is, and so <strong>the</strong> first step is to explain<br />

it. 74<br />

By far <strong>the</strong> commonest traditional conception <strong>of</strong> logic is as a tool for assessing<br />

inferences. To judge whe<strong>the</strong>r an inference succeeds or fails requires criteria <strong>of</strong> adequacy<br />

which <strong>the</strong> inference may be seen ei<strong>the</strong>r to meet or fail. <strong>Logic</strong> is supposed to<br />

73 Abelard’s discussion <strong>of</strong> syllogistic inference under variation <strong>of</strong> tense is treated in [Tweedale,<br />

1976, pp. 298–302]. See also [Rosier-Catach, 1999, pp. 150–156], [Jacobi, 2004, pp. 148–49] and<br />

[Wilks, forthcoming].<br />

74 Otto Bird’s groundbreaking work in topical <strong>the</strong>ory is an especially good point <strong>of</strong> entry into<br />

this material, even if its basic approach is flawed — as argued in [Stump, 1989, pp. 94–95]. See<br />

[Bird, 1959], [Bird, 1960, pp. 141–145] and especially [Bird, 1961].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!