22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

122 Ian Wilks<br />

supply <strong>the</strong>se criteria. As such it serves as an ars iudicandi, a technique for judging.<br />

But it can also be construed as an ars inveniendi, a technique for inventing.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> just providing constraints on what counts as a successful argument, it<br />

may additionally be expected to provide guidance on how to construct a successful<br />

argument in <strong>the</strong> first place, given <strong>the</strong> desired conclusion [Boethius, 1990, p. 1<br />

(4–5)].<br />

The historically seminal text for logic taken in this less common, creative role is<br />

Aristotle’s Topics. Here we find, in somewhat loosely ga<strong>the</strong>red form, advice on how<br />

to advance from <strong>the</strong> yes- or <strong>the</strong> no-position on a debatable yes-or-no question to an<br />

argument for that position. This advance happens through analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relation<br />

between <strong>the</strong> subject and predicate terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition which expresses that<br />

position. Propositions involving different kinds <strong>of</strong> predicative relation and different<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> subject matter will necessitate different kinds <strong>of</strong> advice; <strong>the</strong> basic unit<br />

<strong>of</strong> advice is referred to as a topic, or, in <strong>the</strong> Latin, a locus. There are, <strong>of</strong> course,<br />

many topics, and <strong>the</strong> challenge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> commentators is to impose some order on<br />

this pr<strong>of</strong>usion <strong>of</strong> material.<br />

Topics for Aristotle come in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> a general instruction for argument<br />

formation, with some kind <strong>of</strong> accompanying reason for <strong>the</strong> instruction. 75 Or <strong>the</strong>y<br />

come in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> an instruction alone without <strong>the</strong> reason, or just as a reason<br />

expressed in such a way as to suggest <strong>the</strong> instruction which it justifies [Green-<br />

Pedersen, 1984, p. 21]. Boethius tries to standardize this presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

topics by using two key organizing conceptions: <strong>the</strong> maxima propositio (“maximal<br />

proposition”), and <strong>the</strong> differentia (distinguishing principle). I will consider <strong>the</strong>se<br />

in turn.<br />

The maximal proposition is <strong>the</strong> principle which shows <strong>the</strong> arguer how to identify<br />

a salient fact about one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> terms: a fact which reveals how that term may be<br />

put in <strong>the</strong> desired predicative relation to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r term. Here are some Boethian<br />

examples <strong>of</strong> maximal propositions. (i) Say one wishes to show that trees are<br />

not animals. This may be derived by using <strong>the</strong> following principle, i.e., maximal<br />

proposition: What <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genus does not belong to is not a species<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genus defined [Boethius, 1990, pp. 29 (18–19)]. With this principle in view<br />

one may <strong>the</strong>n note that an animal is an animate substance capable <strong>of</strong> perceiving,<br />

and fur<strong>the</strong>r that a tree is not an animate substance capable <strong>of</strong> perceiving. The<br />

conclusion follows from <strong>the</strong> maximal proposition plus <strong>the</strong> two ensuing facts. (ii)<br />

Say one wishes to show that justice is natural. This maximal proposition will serve:<br />

Those things whose efficient causes are natural are <strong>the</strong>mselves natural [Boethius,<br />

1990, p. 35 (9–10)]. With this principle in view one may <strong>the</strong>n note that <strong>the</strong><br />

society <strong>of</strong> men is natural, and fur<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong> society <strong>of</strong> men is <strong>the</strong> efficient cause<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice. The conclusion follows from <strong>the</strong> maximal proposition plus <strong>the</strong> two<br />

ensuing facts. (iii) Say one wishes to argue that <strong>the</strong> rulers <strong>of</strong> cities should not be<br />

chosen by lot. This maximal proposition will serve: What occurs in a thing must<br />

75 In [Stump, 1978, p. 167] we find a slightly different language for expressing this distinction:<br />

she speaks <strong>of</strong> “a strategy or line <strong>of</strong> argument or tack to take” as opposed to “a principle or a law<br />

that explains or justifies <strong>the</strong> strategy.”

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!