22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 95<br />

because <strong>the</strong>re is no straightforward basis for construing <strong>the</strong>m as generating understandings<br />

and denoting as names and verbs do. And yet <strong>the</strong>y clearly play some<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> semantic role within <strong>the</strong> proposition.<br />

One approach is to argue, against intuitions, that indefinites signify just as<br />

names and verbs do, and preserve this signification even when taken in isolation<br />

from o<strong>the</strong>r words. So what is <strong>the</strong> isolated meaning <strong>of</strong> “<strong>of</strong>”? Since it brings to<br />

mind nothing in particular, some who adopt this approach say that it signifies all<br />

things: “‘Of’ said by itself signifies all things, in that anything is <strong>of</strong> those things”<br />

[Abelard, 1927, p. 337 (14-15); Abelard, 2006, 02.17]. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, anything at<br />

all can be said to be <strong>of</strong>, because one can always identify a group to which it belongs<br />

and <strong>the</strong>n identify it as being <strong>of</strong> that group. So <strong>the</strong> word when taken in isolation<br />

has a specifiable, albeit very broad, signification. When <strong>the</strong> word is <strong>the</strong>n taken<br />

in context with o<strong>the</strong>r words, this universal signification will be limited (reducitur)<br />

and made definite (certificatur) through <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> a name. In <strong>the</strong> phrase “<strong>of</strong><br />

man,” for example, <strong>the</strong> word “<strong>of</strong>” would presumably signify only men [Abelard,<br />

1927, p. 337 (15–16); Abelard, 2006, 02.17].<br />

Against this approach Abelard proposes ano<strong>the</strong>r, which he prefers, and which<br />

indeed seems more intuitive. He simply denies that indefinites preserve signification<br />

when taken in isolation from o<strong>the</strong>r words — and so presumably signify<br />

nothing when said in isolation, as opposed to everything. These words, ra<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

are established for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> co-signifying alongside o<strong>the</strong>r words, and when put<br />

alongside <strong>the</strong>m acquire signification, just as consonants by <strong>the</strong>mselves make no<br />

sound, but acquire sound when uttered alongside vowels [Abelard, 1927, p. 337<br />

(37–40); Abelard, 2006, 02.19]. What Abelard means by indefinite signification,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore, seems to be latent signification. This latent signification is realized<br />

by placement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word in an appropriate context. Now context does not just<br />

render <strong>the</strong> signification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se words more precise; it does that much already<br />

for names and verbs [Abelard, 1927, pp. 337 (41)–338 (3); Abelard, 2006, 02.20;<br />

Nuchelmans, 1973, pp. 140-141], and must do more for indefinites. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

hand context does not simply assign <strong>the</strong> indefinite <strong>the</strong> same signification as some<br />

adjoining definite, since that would yield two words that signify exactly <strong>the</strong> same,<br />

producing a semantic redundancy [Abelard, 1970, p. 119 (20–23)]. Abelard gives<br />

several examples <strong>of</strong> how <strong>the</strong> real but latent signification <strong>of</strong> indefinites emerges by<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir use in context — as when we say that something is “<strong>of</strong> iron,” and mean that<br />

it is made out <strong>of</strong> iron; this is to say more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing than simply to say it is iron.<br />

The presence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> preposition is what makes this difference [Abelard, 1927, p.<br />

338 (24–26); Abelard 2006, 02.24]. 24<br />

By contrast with <strong>the</strong>se indefinite words, names and verbs are both classified as<br />

definites. Their signification is more than latent. It is analysable even with <strong>the</strong><br />

words taken in separation. Of <strong>the</strong> two, names are <strong>the</strong> simpler case. Abelard’s semantic<br />

account <strong>of</strong> names is essentially given already in his discussion <strong>of</strong> universals,<br />

24 Abelard’s account <strong>of</strong> indefinites is commented on elsewhere: [Nuchelmans, 1973, pp. 140–<br />

142], [D¸ambska, 1977], [Jolivet, 1982, pp. 53–56], [Mews, 1985, pp. 83–84], [de Rijk, 1986, pp.<br />

86-87], [Pinzani, 2003, 65–67], [Rosier-Catach, 2003a, pp. 74–79] and [Wilks, forthcoming].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!