22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

538 Simo Knuuttila<br />

‘Socrates necessarily sits when he sits’ is true in <strong>the</strong> first case but false in <strong>the</strong><br />

second case. Perhaps he means that while <strong>the</strong> modal status <strong>of</strong> a proposition pertaining<br />

to a temporally definite event is basically independent <strong>of</strong> temporal changes,<br />

it can be changeable when <strong>the</strong> modal qualification is evaluated from a temporal<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view. Things which are not necessary now may be so to-morrow. This is in<br />

agreement with Abelard’s view about unchangeable metaphysical necessities and<br />

possibilities and temporal modalities which are associated with real potencies. 110<br />

After Abelard, an <strong>of</strong>ten discussed <strong>the</strong>ory about time and modality was associated<br />

with <strong>the</strong> distinction between temporal modalities per se and per accidens.<br />

Per se necessary propositions were said to be true whenever <strong>the</strong>y were uttered and<br />

per accidens necessary propositions, true past tense singular propositions referring<br />

to a definite event, were unchangeably true after having begun to be true. The<br />

same analysis was applied to impossible propositions as well. 111<br />

2.4 Modal Conversion<br />

While <strong>the</strong> conversion <strong>of</strong> assertoric propositions was frequently discussed in early<br />

medieval logic, <strong>the</strong> modal conversions were not <strong>of</strong>ten dealt with before <strong>the</strong> Prior<br />

Analytics began to be used in logic teaching in <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century. One earlier<br />

example is Peter Abelard’s remark that modal propositions in <strong>the</strong> divided<br />

sense are only convertible into assertoric propositions, not into modal propositions;<br />

for example, ‘For every man it is possible to run’ converts into ‘Something<br />

for which it is possible to run is a man’. 112 This was found problematic when<br />

it was realized that conversion <strong>of</strong> modals into modals played an important role<br />

in Aristotle’s modal syllogistics which seemed to concentrate on modalities in <strong>the</strong><br />

divided sense. 113 According to Aristotle (An. pr. I.3), necessity propositions are<br />

converted in <strong>the</strong> same way as <strong>the</strong> corresponding assertoric propositions: a universal<br />

affirmative predication (AaB) implies a converted particular predication (BiA),<br />

a particular affirmative predication (AiB) is equivalent with a converted predication<br />

(BiA), and a universal negative predication (AeB) is converted into universal<br />

negative predication (BeA). The first conversion was called accidental and <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs simple. While <strong>the</strong>se rules are not problematic with respect to modals in<br />

<strong>the</strong> compound sense, Aristotle employed <strong>the</strong>m in proving modal syllogisms some<br />

<strong>of</strong> which seem to be acceptable only when <strong>the</strong> premises are modal propositions in<br />

110 Abelard <strong>of</strong>ten thinks <strong>of</strong> possibility in terms <strong>of</strong> potency attaching to things <strong>of</strong> a particular<br />

species; see J. Marenbon, ‘Abelard’s Concept <strong>of</strong> Possibility’ in B. Mojsisch and O. Pluta (eds.),<br />

Historia philosophiae medii aevi: Studien zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters (Amsterdam<br />

and Philadelphia: Gruener, 1991), 595-609, reprinted in Marenbon 2000; for <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong><br />

metaphysical alternatives, see C.J. Martin, ‘Abelard on Modality: Some Posibilities and Some<br />

Puzzles’, T. Buchheim et al. (eds. 2001), 97-124; Martin 2003.<br />

111 See de Rijk II-1, 371; II-2; 429.1-10; 481.22-482.14; Roger Bacon, Summulae dialectices 2.1.6,<br />

366-72; William <strong>of</strong> Sherwood, Introductiones in logicam 41.8-16, trans. Kretzmann 1966, 41, and<br />

note 16 above.<br />

112 Super Perihermenias 11.17-12.20.<br />

113 For this view <strong>of</strong> modal syllogistics, see Summe Metenses in de Rijk 1967, II-1, 468; Dialectica<br />

Monacensis, de Rijk 1967, II-2, 480.10-16; Lambert <strong>of</strong> Auxerre, <strong>Logic</strong>a 30.17-23.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!