22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

512 Simo Knuuttila<br />

by what he does at o<strong>the</strong>r times. According to Boethius, this shows that sitting<br />

as such does not inhere in Socrates by necessity (II.242.22-243.2). Many twelfth<br />

and thirteenth century authors applied this analysis in discussing <strong>the</strong> sentence ‘A<br />

standing man can sit’, adding to <strong>the</strong> true divided (or de re) reading ‘at ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

time’ or something similar. 15 Ano<strong>the</strong>r Boethian strategy was to refer to antecedent<br />

contingency; I shall return to this in 1.3 below.<br />

Even though <strong>the</strong>re are many examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> frequential use <strong>of</strong> modal terms in<br />

Western authors from Boethius to Thomas Aquinas, <strong>the</strong>y did not define modal<br />

terms through <strong>the</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> various degrees <strong>of</strong> generality or changing and unchanging<br />

truth. 16 These aspects <strong>of</strong> modalities were regarded as concomitant ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

definitional. Modifying Boethius’s classification <strong>of</strong> ancient <strong>the</strong>ories from this point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view, Thomas Aquinas writes that:<br />

Some who distinguished <strong>the</strong>m by results – for example Diodorus – said<br />

15 See, for example, <strong>the</strong> anonymous texts in De Rijk 1962, 210.10-17; 311.8-15; 316.1-7; 613.23-8;<br />

De Rijk 1967 (II.2), 687.28-688.1; William <strong>of</strong> Sherwood, Introductiones in logicam, ed. M.Grabmann<br />

in Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Phil.-hist. Abteilung<br />

1937, 10 (Munich: Verlag der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1937), 90.11-24, trans.<br />

with an introduction and notes by N. Kretzmann in William <strong>of</strong> Sherwood’s Introduction to <strong>Logic</strong><br />

(Minneapolis: <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Minnesota Press, 1966), 141-2; Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain, Tractatus VII.68,<br />

70-1; Lambert <strong>of</strong> Auxerre, <strong>Logic</strong>a, ed. F. Alassio (Florence: La Nuova Italia, 1971), 158.<br />

16 For an equation <strong>of</strong> modal and temporal notions (necessarily-always, possibly-sometimes), see<br />

Averroes’s commentary <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s De caelo in Aristotelis opera cum Averrois commentariis<br />

(Venice 1562-74), vol. V, 84A-D, 87H-M, and Avicenna’s treatise al-Masa’il, quoted in T. Street,<br />

‘Fahraddīn Ar-Rāzī’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Avicennan <strong>Logic</strong>’ in D. Perler and U. Rudolph (eds.) Logik und<br />

Theologie. Das Organon im arabischen und lateinischen Mittelalter, Studien und Texte zur<br />

Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 84 (Leiden: Brill, 2005), 104. Fur<strong>the</strong>r typical examples are<br />

<strong>the</strong> principles that if something can be destroyed, it will be destroyed (Moses Maimonides, The<br />

Guide <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Perplexed, trans. with introduction and notes by Sh. Pines (Chicago: <strong>University</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1974), II, 247, 249; Thomas Aquinas, Summa <strong>the</strong>ologiae, ed. P. Caramello<br />

(Turin: Marietti, 1948-50) I.2.3; In Post. an. I.13, 117; cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics XII.6),<br />

what is possible with respect to a species will be actualized (Moses Maimonides in a letter to<br />

Samuel ibn Tibbon, quoted in Ch.H. Manekin, ‘Problems <strong>of</strong> ‘Plenitude’ in Maimonides and<br />

Gersonides’ in R. Link-Salinger, R. Long and Ch.H. Manekin (eds.), A Straight Path: Studies in<br />

Medieval Philosophy and Culture. Essays in Honor <strong>of</strong> Arthur Hyman (Washington: Catholic<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> America Press, 1988), 187, and that universal propositions are false and particular<br />

propositions are true in contingent matter (De Rijk 1967, II.2, 115.5-12; 138.24-6; Albert <strong>the</strong><br />

Great, Commentarius in Perihermenias, inOpera omnia, ed. A. Borgnet, vol. I (Paris: Vivès,<br />

1890), 5.6, 422, and <strong>the</strong> texts mentioned in note 8 above). Gersonides also assumed that all<br />

genuine possibilities will be actualized; see The Book <strong>of</strong> Correct Syllogism I.1.14 in The <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

Gersonides. A Translation <strong>of</strong> Sefer ha-Heqqesh ha-Yashar (The Book <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Correct Syllogism),<br />

with introduction, commentary, and analytical glossary by Ch.H. Manekin, The New Syn<strong>the</strong>se<br />

Historical Library 40 (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992). One <strong>of</strong> distinctions between modalities per<br />

se and per accidens, which were employed in logical treatises, was based on <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong><br />

modal status <strong>of</strong> a temporally indefinite tensed proposition may be changeable. According to<br />

<strong>the</strong> early thirteenth-century <strong>Logic</strong>a ‘Ut dicit’, true future tense singular propositions referring to<br />

non-existent future things, such as ‘The Antichrist will be existent’, are necessary per accidens,<br />

for <strong>the</strong>y cannot have been false in <strong>the</strong> past nor false now, though <strong>the</strong>y will be false in <strong>the</strong> future<br />

(de Rijk 1967, II.2, 390.21-2);‘necessarily’ is said to mean <strong>the</strong> same as ‘in all times’ in this treatise<br />

(411.8-9). It was more usual to associate accidental necessities and impossibilities with past tense<br />

singular propositions; see note 111 below. Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain wrote that ‘Antichrist has not been’<br />

will be accidentally impossible, though it is true now (Tractatus IX.4).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!