22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Paradoxes <strong>of</strong> Self-reference 585<br />

cannot be, because from conceding only <strong>the</strong> sentence ‘a falsehood is conceded’ and<br />

nothing else, a paradox would follow. [Anonymous, 2001, 203].<br />

In both <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se cases, <strong>the</strong> paradox can be avoiding by <strong>the</strong> respondent’s refusal<br />

to go into such situation, since <strong>the</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> obligations allow such a move. Without<br />

respondent’s acceptance nothing can be posited, and without him conceding <strong>the</strong><br />

crucial sentence nothing dangerous is conceded, and no self-reference arises.<br />

After discussing <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> positing ‘a falsehood is posited’ (let us call it ‘p’)<br />

alone, <strong>the</strong> author goes into a discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opponent wishing to posit a molecular<br />

sentence containing ‘p’. The rules concerning <strong>the</strong>se situations are quite simple,<br />

and again <strong>the</strong> idea is to avoid <strong>the</strong> paradox. The disjunction p ∨ q can be posited<br />

if q is true but not if it is false. Similarly, <strong>the</strong> conjunction p&q can be posited if<br />

q is false but not if it is true. The underlying idea is, <strong>of</strong> course, that it should be<br />

possible to assign truth values without problems. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disjunction<br />

that is true because <strong>of</strong> q, it can be entertained that <strong>the</strong> positum is true and thus<br />

‘a falsehood is posited’ is false. Similarly, in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> positing <strong>the</strong> conjunction<br />

having an unambiguously false conjunct, it can be entertained that ‘a falsehood is<br />

posited’ is true [Anonymous, 2001, 200–201]. At this point it may also be pointed<br />

out that Insolubilia Monacensia too addresses <strong>the</strong> issue and resolves it similarly.<br />

According to that text, ‘I utter a falsehood or God exists’ can be granted because<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter disjunct, while ‘I utter a falsehood and God exists’ is insoluble and<br />

must be cancelled because its truth would require <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first conjuct<br />

[De Rijk, 1966, 109–111].<br />

According to a fur<strong>the</strong>r rule in <strong>the</strong> Emmeran Treatise, if <strong>the</strong> opponent wants to<br />

posit a material equivalence between <strong>the</strong> positum and some o<strong>the</strong>r sentence, <strong>the</strong><br />

respondent must check whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> sentence at issue is true or false: if it is false,<br />

<strong>the</strong> positum may not be accepted. If <strong>the</strong> opponent wants to posit something like<br />

“<strong>the</strong> positum and [<strong>the</strong> first sentence] put forward are similar [in truth value]”, <strong>the</strong><br />

respondent can only accept <strong>the</strong> positum in case <strong>the</strong> first sentence will be true.<br />

Unfortunately <strong>the</strong> author does not recognize that this ruling allows <strong>the</strong> opponent<br />

to trap <strong>the</strong> respondent who maybe does not know what <strong>the</strong> opponent is going to<br />

put forward as <strong>the</strong> first sentence [Anonymous, 2001, 201–202].<br />

These rules about molecular sentences containing self-reference show that <strong>the</strong><br />

intention is not to prohibit reference to <strong>the</strong> positum in <strong>the</strong> positum itself. It is<br />

not <strong>the</strong> self-reference that is taken to be problematic, but <strong>the</strong> possibly ensuing<br />

paradoxes. Thus, <strong>the</strong> suggestions do not amount to even trying to give a solution<br />

to <strong>the</strong> paradox. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> author sketches ways <strong>of</strong> seeing how it could arise and<br />

how it can be avoided in advance. The picture gets very complicated because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

two-tier structure involving <strong>the</strong> technical disputational context and <strong>the</strong> discussion<br />

outside <strong>the</strong> disputation. Somewhat interestingly, <strong>the</strong> author does not pay attention<br />

to how self-referential paradoxes could arise within <strong>the</strong> technical disputation itself.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> later treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> obligations technique self-referential structures<br />

become more rare or merely apparent. 5 Occurrences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence ‘<strong>the</strong> positum<br />

5 As an outstanding exception, Obligationes Parisiensis contains material similar to that found<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Emmeran Treatise. Cf. [De Rijk, 1975].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!