22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Paradoxes <strong>of</strong> Self-reference 591<br />

(2) ‘a’ signifies that what is uttered by Socrates is false P2<br />

(3) ‘a’ signifies that ‘a’ is false T1.2<br />

(4) ‘a’ signifies itself to be false P2<br />

(5) ‘a’ signifies itself to be true T2<br />

(6) ‘a’ is false T2<br />

The edge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument really comes from <strong>the</strong> fact that if a similar reasoning is<br />

applied to ‘b’, or <strong>the</strong> proposition put forward to you in <strong>the</strong> disputation, it will not<br />

go through. The beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reasoning works, <strong>of</strong> course, in <strong>the</strong> same way:<br />

(1)* ‘b’ signifies that Socrates utters a falsehood<br />

(2)* ‘b’ signifies that what is uttered by Socrates false P2<br />

(3)* ‘b’ signifies that ‘a’ is false T1.2<br />

But after this line it is clear that <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pronoun ‘itself’ would be<br />

fallacious. For ‘a’ isnot‘b’, it is a different token <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same type. And because<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no self-reference, Bradwardine’s second <strong>the</strong>sis (T2) cannot be used. The<br />

true claim that Socrates utters a falsehood gets separated from <strong>the</strong> false one.<br />

Bradwardine’s solution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> paradox amounts thus to exact logical way <strong>of</strong><br />

spelling out <strong>the</strong> fact that whereas ‘a’ signifies something about itself, <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

such self-reference for ‘b’. Thus, <strong>the</strong> meanings <strong>of</strong> ‘a’ and ‘b’ differ, and <strong>the</strong>y differ<br />

so that ‘b’ means almost everything ‘a’ does, except that ‘a’ additionally means<br />

that ‘a’ is true. To be sure, ‘b’ does not mean that ‘a’ istrue,anditdoesnot<br />

mean that ‘b’ is true.<br />

Even if this is <strong>the</strong> core <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> solution, working it out in an acceptable way was<br />

not a simple project. When we look at Bradwardine’s successors, we find that in<br />

general <strong>the</strong>y did not buy Bradwardine’s (T2). There were exceptions, though. At<br />

least Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony and to some extent John Buridan, as we will see, accepted<br />

(T2) in virtue <strong>of</strong> accepting <strong>the</strong> stronger claim that all sentences signify <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

truth, but this seems not to have been Bradwardine’s intention. He appears to<br />

say that it is only <strong>the</strong> paradoxical sentences that signify <strong>the</strong>ir own truth. 19<br />

Bradwardine’s pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> crucial <strong>the</strong>sis (T2) is difficult to spell out, but it is<br />

really <strong>the</strong> most important part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> solution, since without pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis just<br />

is not acceptable. With <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>, Bradwardine can rely only on (P2), which is<br />

much easier to accept as it stands. To prove (T2), he first proves that any sentence<br />

which signifies that it itself is not true also signifies that it itself is true. Then he<br />

extends <strong>the</strong> result to sentences that signify <strong>the</strong>ir own falsehood. As <strong>the</strong> last part<br />

he proves <strong>the</strong> final bit that because <strong>the</strong>se sentences signify <strong>the</strong>ir own truth, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are false. The crucial part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic is to found in <strong>the</strong> first part, which works<br />

with <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> sentence ei<strong>the</strong>r does or does not mean something<br />

19 The agreements and differences between Bradwardine, Buridan and Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony have<br />

been spelled out in detail by Stephen Read in [Read, 2002].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!