22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Latin Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> to 1100 5<br />

on logic in Latin. Two <strong>of</strong> his logical works survive: a translation <strong>of</strong> Porphyry’s<br />

Isagoge (used by Boethius for his first commentary) [Hadot, 1971, 371-80] and On<br />

Definition (De definitione/definitionibus [Hadot, 1971, 331-62] that was wrongly<br />

attributed to Boethius in <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages. Victorinus also wrote a now lost<br />

commentary on Cicero’s Topics (Reconstruction in [Hadot, 1971, 118-41]), which<br />

is mentioned critically by Boethius in his own commentary on <strong>the</strong> same work, and<br />

from Cassiodorus we know that he wrote, just as Boethius would do, a treatise on<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms. (See [Hadot, 1971, 323-7] for an assemblage <strong>of</strong> possible<br />

traces <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> treatise.) According to Cassiodorus, Victorinus also translated <strong>the</strong><br />

Categories and On Interpretation and wrote a long commentary on it. But <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is no trace <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se works, and it has been argued that Cassiodorus (whose text<br />

presents problems: see below, subsection 2.3, pages 21–22) is misleading here<br />

[Hadot, 1971, 105-8].<br />

Victorinus placed logic within <strong>the</strong> framework <strong>of</strong> rhetoric. Study <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Isagoge,<br />

Categories and On Interpretation led, not as in <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian organon, primarily<br />

to syllogistic (in <strong>the</strong> Prior Analytics) and its use in demonstration (in <strong>the</strong> Posterior<br />

Analytics), but to <strong>the</strong> topics, as expounded by Cicero. And, for Victorinus — to<br />

judge from his words as probably reported by Cassiodorus [Cassiodorus, 1937, 127]<br />

— it is <strong>the</strong> very fact that <strong>the</strong> Ciceronian topics presents arguments that are suited,<br />

not just to philosophers, but to orators, lawyers and poets as well, which makes<br />

<strong>the</strong>m so precious. On Definition and <strong>the</strong> (lost) treatise on hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms<br />

can be seen as continuations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> commentary on Cicero’s Topics, since each<br />

corresponds to a part <strong>of</strong> Cicero’s text (definition: §§26-37; hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms<br />

53-7) not treated in <strong>the</strong> commentary itself, which covers only half <strong>the</strong> work. On<br />

Definition draws extensively on Cicero himself in categorizing and explaining <strong>the</strong><br />

different sorts <strong>of</strong> definition — rhetorical definition, philosophical definition (which<br />

is based on <strong>the</strong> five predicables: genus, species, differentia, proprium — i.e. an<br />

accident that distinguishes a species, such as ability to laugh in humans — and<br />

accident) and o<strong>the</strong>r types <strong>of</strong> definition, such as that from a thing’s parts, which<br />

does not explain what <strong>the</strong> things are, but gives some understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. It has<br />

been suggested that here a work by Porphyry may have been <strong>the</strong> source. [Hadot,<br />

1968, I, 482-8]<br />

The ‘Ten Categories’ ([Kenny, 2005, 128-33])<br />

The Categorial Decem(Ten Categories), as it came to be called, probably owed<br />

some <strong>of</strong> its early medieval popularity to <strong>the</strong> fact that it came to be attributed to<br />

Augustine. But it also deserved to be used, because it is an excellent work for<br />

beginners in logic trying to understand Aristotle. The real author is unknown,<br />

but in a couple <strong>of</strong> comments (Aristotle, 1961, 137:20-1; 175:18-9) he makes clear<br />

that he belongs to <strong>the</strong> circle <strong>of</strong> Themistius, <strong>the</strong> fourth-century philosopher and<br />

statesman who was perhaps <strong>the</strong> last member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ancient Peripatetic school.<br />

(Anthony Kenny has suggested that <strong>the</strong> author <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> paraphrase might in fact be<br />

Marius Victorinus: [Kenny, 2005, 130-3].)<br />

The paraphraser reveals his approach when (Aristotle, 1961, 148:33 — 149:2),

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!