22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

516 Simo Knuuttila<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> potency and impotency should be treated in <strong>the</strong> same way. According<br />

to Anselm, ‘A is necessarily B’ properly ascribes a constraint to A and ‘A is possibly<br />

B’ properly ascribes a capacity to A. Modal terms proper refer to properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> things, such as <strong>the</strong> power to bring something about, or constraints caused by<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r things. If modal terms are used in ano<strong>the</strong>r way, <strong>the</strong>y are used improperly.<br />

Since Anselm regards <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> capacity as <strong>the</strong> basic modal notion, something<br />

is necessary in an improper sense with respect to causes which cannot prevent it,<br />

and something is similarly impossible with respect to causes which cannot bring<br />

it about. There are no constraining necessities proper in God, and divine impossibilities<br />

are similarly analysed by referring to external impossibilities. In trying<br />

to solve problems associated with <strong>the</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> freedom, sin and grace, Anselm<br />

also employed <strong>the</strong> distinction between full and partial potencies. The shortcomings<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se analyses and some artificial constructions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> modal<br />

statements based on <strong>the</strong> distinction between proper and improper capacity show<br />

that <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> potency is too narrow a basis for modal semantics. 24<br />

1.3 Temporal modalities<br />

A third ancient modal paradigm in Boethius meant for discussing singular possibilities<br />

could be called <strong>the</strong> diachronic model <strong>of</strong> modality. In chapter 9 <strong>of</strong> Peri<br />

hermeneias, Aristotle tries to qualify <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present — a corollary<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> simultaneous alternatives in his <strong>the</strong>ory — stating that not everything<br />

which is actual is necessary simpliciter, without qualification (19a23-4). If<br />

necessity without qualification means ‘necessary even without <strong>the</strong> temporal qualification’,<br />

as Boethius reads it in his first commentary, Aristotle’s point would be<br />

that <strong>the</strong> temporal necessity <strong>of</strong> actual events does not imply that such events are<br />

necessary in <strong>the</strong>mselves in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>y always take place in similar circumstances.<br />

25 As already mentioned, this is a problematic attempt to qualify <strong>the</strong><br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> a definite singular event with <strong>the</strong> help <strong>of</strong> frequential considerations.<br />

Some medieval and modern interpreters have opted for ano<strong>the</strong>r interpretation:<br />

Aristotle wanted to show that <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> an event at a certain time does<br />

not imply that it would have been antecedently necessary. There are some places<br />

in which Aristotle speaks about genuine singular possibilities with respect to definite<br />

future points <strong>of</strong> time which may be realized or remain unrealized (De int.<br />

19a13-17, EN III.5, 1114a17-19, Met. VI.3). 26 This idea <strong>of</strong> diachronic modalities<br />

was considered important in <strong>the</strong> later Peripatetic tradition. It was argued against<br />

Stoic determinism that <strong>the</strong>re are genuine future alternatives which remain open<br />

24 See E. Serene, ‘Anselm’s Modal Conceptions’ in S. Knuuttila (ed.), Reforging <strong>the</strong> Great<br />

Chain <strong>of</strong> Being, Syn<strong>the</strong>se Historical Library 20 (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981), 117-62; S. Knuuttila,<br />

‘Anselm on Modality’ in B. Davies and B. Leftow (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Anselm<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 2004), 111-31.<br />

25 See Hintikka 1973, 147-175; Boethius, In Periherm. I.121.25-122.4.<br />

26 This is a central <strong>the</strong>me in S. Waterlow, Passage and Possibility: A Study <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

Modal Concepts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982); see also G.H. von Wright, Truth, Knowledge,<br />

and Modality (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984), 72-8.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!