22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

460 Catarina Dutilh Novaes<br />

<strong>the</strong> subdivisions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> different modes <strong>of</strong> supposition are considerably more complicated<br />

than <strong>the</strong> division between personal and material supposition (recall that<br />

Marsilius, following Buridan, does not recognize simple supposition as a class <strong>of</strong> its<br />

own and views <strong>the</strong> supposition for mental terms as a kind <strong>of</strong> material supposition).<br />

Here is a tree representing his divisions:<br />

Material<br />

Discrete<br />

Merely confused<br />

Material<br />

Personal<br />

Personal<br />

Supposition<br />

Confused and<br />

distributive<br />

Confused<br />

Material Personal<br />

Common<br />

Determinate<br />

Material Personal<br />

We thus have four kinds <strong>of</strong> material supposition, just as much as four kinds<br />

<strong>of</strong> personal supposition. Thereby, Marsilius is able to present a more fine-grained<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon <strong>of</strong> terms standing for o<strong>the</strong>r terms. Indeed, a term may<br />

stand for:<br />

• one specific non-ultimate significate 28 only – discrete material supposition,<br />

for example if I say ‘This ‘man’ is written in red’ pointing at a specific<br />

occurrence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word ‘man’ (cf. [Marsilius <strong>of</strong> Inghen, 1983, 55]);<br />

• any non-ultimate sigificate in a disjunctive way — determinate material supposition,<br />

for example if I say ‘Man is written on this page’ meaning that <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is at least one occurrence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word ‘man’ in a given page (cf. [Marsilius<br />

<strong>of</strong> Inghen, 1983, 57]);<br />

• any non-ultimate significate with disjunction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term — merely confused<br />

material supposition, for example with ‘Only man is a monosyllabic word’,<br />

from which follows ‘Only this [occurrence <strong>of</strong>] man or that [occurrence <strong>of</strong>]<br />

man etc. is a monosyllabic word’ (cf. [Marsilius <strong>of</strong> Inghen, 1983, 59]);<br />

28 For Marsilius, following Buridan, <strong>the</strong> ultimate significates <strong>of</strong> terms are <strong>the</strong> things that fall<br />

under <strong>the</strong>m, such as men for ‘man’, concepts for ‘concept’ etc., and <strong>the</strong> non-ultimate sigificates<br />

<strong>of</strong> terms are <strong>the</strong> things that <strong>the</strong>y also signify — <strong>the</strong> corresponding mental, spoken and written<br />

terms — but not ultimately.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!