22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 233<br />

The significance <strong>of</strong> suppositional mode being local will emerge when we discuss<br />

rules <strong>of</strong> inference below, and when in <strong>the</strong> next section we contrast <strong>the</strong> early <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

with <strong>the</strong> later, in which modes <strong>of</strong> supposition are global, not local.<br />

7.5 Causes <strong>of</strong> Distribution and Confusion<br />

All scholars agree that nei<strong>the</strong>r confusion nor distribution can occur unless it is<br />

caused to occur. Generally, it was thought that <strong>the</strong>y must be caused to occur by<br />

some sign which has scope over <strong>the</strong> term in question. 90 We look here at some 13 th<br />

century accounts.<br />

Confusion and distribution need to be caused, but determinacy does not; this is<br />

because a common term that is unaffected by any sign is determinate by default.<br />

It is also immobile by default. Its status can be changed by <strong>the</strong> addition <strong>of</strong> some<br />

sign, though not just any old sign; a particular sign such as ‘some’ leaves its<br />

determinate status unchanged.<br />

Signs o<strong>the</strong>r than particular ones can affect<br />

Confusion ...causing it or undoing it,<br />

Distribution ...causing it or undoing it,<br />

Mobility ...causing it or undoing it.<br />

For example, ‘every’ in <strong>the</strong> universal affirmative form confuses and distributes and<br />

makes mobile <strong>the</strong> subject to which it is adjoined; it confuses <strong>the</strong> predicate without<br />

distributing it and without making it mobile. The ‘no’ in <strong>the</strong> universal negative<br />

confuses and distributes both <strong>the</strong> subject term to which it is adjoined and <strong>the</strong><br />

predicate term, and makes <strong>the</strong>m both mobile.<br />

Sherwood gives three rules for confusion and distribution [IL V.13.1 (117).]<br />

(The rules presuppose that a term starts out determinate by default.):<br />

[A] every distributive sign confuses <strong>the</strong> term immediately adjoining it<br />

confusedly and distributively.<br />

[B] an affirmative [distributive] sign confuses <strong>the</strong> remote term merely<br />

confusedly.<br />

[C] a negative [distributive] sign confuses <strong>the</strong> remote term confusedly<br />

and distributively.<br />

Thus this follows: ‘nomanisanass;<strong>the</strong>reforenomanisthisass’. But<br />

this does not follow: ‘every man is an animal; <strong>the</strong>refore every man is<br />

this animal’.<br />

Sherwood’s rules say nothing about mobility, which is what is at issue in <strong>the</strong><br />

examples he gives. (The question is whe<strong>the</strong>r one may descend under ‘ass’ or<br />

‘animal’.) I think that he is presupposing a rule about mobility, which I will call<br />

D:<br />

90The notion <strong>of</strong> scope here is a modern one; I use it here to sum up what seems to me to be<br />

<strong>the</strong> medieval practices. Certain writers thought that confusion or distribution could be caused<br />

without a sign, by <strong>the</strong> will <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> speaker (such as giving distributive supposition to <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

<strong>of</strong> an indefinite proposition such as ‘A donkey is an animal’). Cf. [Barney et al., 1997].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!