22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

464 Catarina Dutilh Novaes<br />

(2 ′ ) would no longer be preserved: B would have merely confused supposition in<br />

(2 ′ ), whereas it ought to have determinate supposition, as in (1).<br />

Thus, nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se rules is able to preserve both equivalences: thus formulated,<br />

a rule concerning <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation upon a term originally with<br />

confused and distributive supposition ei<strong>the</strong>r preserves <strong>the</strong> equivalence between (1)<br />

and (2 ′ ) (Ockham’s rule) or it preserves <strong>the</strong> equivalence between (3) and (4 ′ )(Buridan’s<br />

rule). This is due to <strong>the</strong> following asymmetry: in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> contradiction 1,<br />

<strong>the</strong> opposition in <strong>the</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> B in each proposition is between determinate<br />

supposition and confused and distributive supposition, whereas in contradiction<br />

2 <strong>the</strong> same opposition is between merely confused supposition and confused and<br />

distributive supposition. Therefore, it would seem impossible to provide a homogeneous<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation (or o<strong>the</strong>r distributive term) upon<br />

terms with confused and distributive supposition (for a systematic approach to<br />

this problem, see part 8 <strong>of</strong> Parson’s contribution to this volume).<br />

However (and fortunately for <strong>the</strong> general robustness <strong>of</strong> supposition <strong>the</strong>ory as a<br />

semantic framework), later masters were well aware <strong>of</strong> this difficulty and proposed<br />

ways to deal with it. Already at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 14 th century, in his popular<br />

commentary to Buridan’s Summulae, John Dorp [1499] proposed a method to<br />

determine <strong>the</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> terms following a negation based on <strong>the</strong> idea that<br />

<strong>the</strong> proposition should be rephrased in such a way that <strong>the</strong> negation would be<br />

all <strong>the</strong> way at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition, in which case <strong>the</strong> usual (i.e. positive)<br />

rules for <strong>the</strong> determination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> personal supposition <strong>of</strong> a term could be applied.<br />

On this approach, ‘[t]he problem <strong>of</strong> assigning <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> supposition to a term<br />

following a negation becomes that <strong>of</strong> determining a procedure for bringing negative<br />

sentences into a non-ordinary form [one where <strong>the</strong> negation only precedes <strong>the</strong> verb]<br />

such that <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> each term remains unchanged.’ [Karger, 1993,<br />

419]<br />

On <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> Dorp’s examples, Karger proposes a reconstruction <strong>of</strong> what this<br />

procedure would be like, essentially based in <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> bringing <strong>the</strong> negation<br />

towards <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition, immediately before <strong>the</strong> verb, and introducing<br />

universally quantifying signs (to recover <strong>the</strong> distributive effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation)<br />

where <strong>the</strong>re was none, and deleting such universally quantifying terms previously<br />

present. Here is an example (cf. [Karger, 1993, 419], and [Read, 1991a, fn. 8] for<br />

Dorp’s text):<br />

Nullum animal omnis homo est (No animal is every man) is rephrased<br />

as<br />

Omne animal homo non est (Every animal a man is not).<br />

Nullum is replaced by Omne, omnis preceding homo in <strong>the</strong> original proposition is<br />

deleted, and <strong>the</strong> negation comes to be followed only by <strong>the</strong> verb est. Now, it is clear<br />

that animal has confused and distributive supposition (which was clear already in<br />

<strong>the</strong> original proposition), but moreover it becomes apparent that homo has merely<br />

confused supposition (as it follows mediately <strong>the</strong> universal sign), whereas in <strong>the</strong><br />

original proposition it would have been unclear (from 3o and 3b alone) whe<strong>the</strong>r it

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!