22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

168 Terence Parsons<br />

1.7 Quantifying <strong>the</strong> Predicate Term; Equipollences<br />

The above is mostly Aristotle’s logic with some <strong>of</strong> its consequences spelled out.<br />

Some medieval authors in <strong>the</strong> 1200’s expanded <strong>the</strong> stock <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s categorical<br />

propositions by allowing quantifier signs to combine with predicate terms, and<br />

allowing not’s to occur more widely, so as to produce propositions like ‘No A is<br />

not every B’, or ‘Not every A some B is not’. I call Aristotle’s forms ‘standard<br />

Aristotelian categorical propositions’, and I call <strong>the</strong> expanded forms ‘categorical<br />

propositions’. The forms <strong>of</strong> categorical propositions will be fur<strong>the</strong>r extended in<br />

section 3.<br />

Along with <strong>the</strong>se expanded forms, writers added a series <strong>of</strong> equipollences —<br />

logically equivalent pairs <strong>of</strong> propositions that differ only in having one part replaced<br />

by an “equivalent” part. These are like contemporary rules <strong>of</strong> quantifier exchange,<br />

such as <strong>the</strong> equivalence <strong>of</strong> ‘∀x’ with ‘∼ ∃x ∼’.<br />

“To reduce [a syllogism] per impossibile is to infer <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> premises<br />

from <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conclusion toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r premise. For suppose<br />

we take <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conclusion <strong>of</strong> this fourth mood (namely, ‘Every stone<br />

is a man’) toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> major premise and construct a syllogism in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

mood <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first figure in this way:<br />

Every man is an animal;<br />

every stone is a man;<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore, every stone is an animal.<br />

“This conclusion is <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> minor premise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourth mood. And this<br />

is what it is to prove something [by reduction] per impossibile.”<br />

These instructions work perfectly provided that conversion by limitation is used in <strong>the</strong> correct<br />

order; from particular to universal in premises, and from particular to universal in conclusions.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!