22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

526 Simo Knuuttila<br />

a disjunction implies that <strong>the</strong> disjuncts are necessary or determinate. 69 This is<br />

close to what Mignucci regards as Boethius’s position.<br />

The commentary on De interpretatione 9in<strong>Logic</strong>a ‘Ingredientibus’ involves<br />

Abelard’s most detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s argument. Chapter<br />

9 is described as a dialectical discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis that in all contradictories one<br />

part is necessarily true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r false. The correct reading <strong>of</strong> this is that <strong>of</strong><br />

all contradictory pairs necessarily one part is true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r false. This does<br />

not imply that one is necessarily true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r necessarily false, although one<br />

is true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r false. 70<br />

Abelard pays attention to some propositions about past and present states <strong>of</strong><br />

affairs <strong>the</strong> truth and falsity <strong>of</strong> which depend on future, such as ‘Socrates is <strong>the</strong><br />

name <strong>of</strong> a man going to eat tomorrow’ or ‘He has spoken falsely’, when this is<br />

said <strong>of</strong> a man who said yesterday that Socrates will eat tomorrow. The truth and<br />

falsity <strong>of</strong> propositions <strong>of</strong> this kind are not knowable without knowledge <strong>of</strong> future<br />

contingent states <strong>of</strong> affairs which are indeterminate and epistemically inaccessible<br />

to human beings. Hence <strong>the</strong> propositions have an indeterminate truth and falsity<br />

and do not differ from future contingent propositions in this respect. In discussing<br />

<strong>the</strong>se examples, Abelard states that ‘Aristotle calls propositions determinately or<br />

indeterminately true with respect to <strong>the</strong> determinate or indeterminate states <strong>of</strong> affairs<br />

<strong>the</strong>y propose’. This terminology is part <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s rational reconstruction<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s discussion; being probably aware that Aristotle did not use <strong>the</strong>se<br />

terms at all, Abelard suggests that Aristotle would consider propositions indeterminately<br />

true or false if <strong>the</strong>ir truth depended on indeterminate future contingent<br />

states <strong>of</strong> affairs. Propositions which propose <strong>the</strong> actual inherence <strong>of</strong> truth in a future<br />

contingent proposition are <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form: “Socrates will eat tomorrow’ is true’.<br />

As far as determinateness is understood in accordance with what Abelard calls<br />

Aristotle’s view, this is no more determinate than ‘Socrates will eat tomorrow’.<br />

As for <strong>the</strong> truth as a present fact, Abelard repeats <strong>the</strong> remark from <strong>the</strong> Dialectica<br />

that one could call this present state <strong>of</strong> affairs determinate and, correspondingly,<br />

<strong>the</strong> propositions determinately true or false. In this sense all true propositions<br />

are determinately true, but this has nothing to do with causal determination.<br />

Abelard also remarks that God knows whe<strong>the</strong>r any proposition is true and false,<br />

and all true propositions are determinately true with respect to this omniscience.<br />

The determinateness in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> divine knowability pertains to truth-values<br />

and truth-makers, but this supranatural knowability does not make things necessary.<br />

71 While <strong>the</strong> truth-values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se propositions are in principle knowable,<br />

human beings cannot know <strong>the</strong>m without supranatural illumination. The present<br />

truth <strong>of</strong> a future contingent proposition implies that what is predicted will obtain<br />

but not that it is determinate, since future contingent states <strong>of</strong> affairs are inde-<br />

69 Dialectica 211.28-32; 212.36-213.7; 221.15-24.<br />

70 <strong>Logic</strong>a ‘Ingredientibus’ 431.13-432.9; 445.22-446.29.<br />

71 <strong>Logic</strong>a ‘Ingredientibus’ 421.28-422.30. For truth and determinateness in Abelard, see also C.<br />

Normore, ‘Future Contingents’ in N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, J. Pinborg (eds.), The Cambridge<br />

<strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong> Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1981), 362-3;<br />

N.T. Lewis, ‘Determinate Truth in Abelard’, Vivarium 25 (1987), 81-109.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!