22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

288 Henrik Lagerlund<br />

term is hence a term that signifies two or more concepts or understandings in <strong>the</strong><br />

intellect. This goes toge<strong>the</strong>r with his view that signification is additive, that is,<br />

<strong>the</strong> signification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> complex term is a sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> signification <strong>of</strong> its simple<br />

parts.<br />

The third division <strong>of</strong> terms (dictionis) is into singular and universal terms. A<br />

term is singular if its signification prohibits it to stand for more than one particular<br />

thing or limits it to only one. His examples are ‘this Peter’, ‘this horse’ or ‘this<br />

tree’. A term is on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand universal if its signification does not prohibit<br />

it to stand for more than one thing, like ‘horse’, ‘tree’ or ‘human being’. He<br />

seems not to distinguish between proper names and singular terms, and given his<br />

example <strong>of</strong> ‘this Peter’ he seems not to think that proper names like ‘Peter’ are<br />

what is nowadays <strong>of</strong>ten called rigid designators. ‘Peter’ is just a universal term<br />

like ‘horse’, which can apply to many.<br />

The fourth division (3.1.8) is between verbs, names and particles. He notes first<br />

that particles do not appear by <strong>the</strong>mselves in <strong>the</strong> intellect only in connection with<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r terms. A verb is different from a name in that it signifies an intention and<br />

a time at which it is done. His example is ‘He struck’, which signifies a striking<br />

<strong>of</strong> something by someone and a past time when this was done. A name does not<br />

signify a time. The last division is between different intentions or meanings <strong>of</strong><br />

terms. He lists five, namely univocal terms, divers terms, that is, many terms for<br />

<strong>the</strong> same thing, multivocal terms, that is, many terms for many things, equivocal<br />

terms, and something he calls convenient (conveniantia) terms. The last is, he<br />

says, something between univocal and equivocal and an example is ‘being’, which<br />

is said <strong>of</strong> both substances and accidents.<br />

The title <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> part <strong>of</strong> Al-Ghazālī’s logic that deals with universal terms is “on<br />

<strong>the</strong> intention <strong>of</strong> universal terms”. In <strong>the</strong> sentence: ‘This human being is white<br />

and an animal’, <strong>the</strong> predication <strong>of</strong> ‘white’ and ‘animal’ <strong>of</strong> ‘human being’ is quite<br />

different. Al-Ghazālī calls <strong>the</strong> first accidental and <strong>the</strong> second essential. To explain<br />

this difference he first explains what essential and accidental mean in <strong>the</strong>se cases.<br />

There are three conditions for essentiality:<br />

(3.1.10) A is essential to B, if B cannot be understood or thought<br />

without A;<br />

(3.1.11) A is essential to B, if A is necessarily prior to B;<br />

(3.1.12) A is essential to B, if B cannot be posited to be without A.<br />

It seems that all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se, (3.1.10)-(3.1.12), must be fulfilled for something to be<br />

essentially something else. The first condition says simply that if we cannot think<br />

about one thing without also necessarily thinking about something else, like in<br />

<strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> human being and animal. Thinking about a human or a horse brings<br />

also <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> an animal into <strong>the</strong> mind. This means that <strong>the</strong>se concepts or<br />

terms are essentially tied. The second condition is a little bit less straightforward,<br />

but he seems to mean, as Aristotle indeed thought, that what is essentially tied<br />

to each o<strong>the</strong>r is also ordered in a special way, namely in <strong>the</strong> sense that animal is<br />

prior to human being and horse. In <strong>the</strong> third condition, <strong>the</strong> idea seems to be that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!