22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

90 Ian Wilks<br />

standings <strong>of</strong> universal and singular . These are differentiated in that <strong>the</strong><br />

understanding pertaining to <strong>the</strong> universal name grasps a common and confused<br />

image <strong>of</strong> many, but <strong>the</strong> understanding which <strong>the</strong> singular word generates grasps<br />

a form which is proper to one and, as it were, singular — that is, related only to<br />

one object (personam)” [Abelard, 1919, p. 21 (27–32)]. The image arising from<br />

many, to which <strong>the</strong> understanding <strong>of</strong> a general term is referenced, is “common<br />

and confused,” while <strong>the</strong> image arising from only one, to which <strong>the</strong> understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> a singular term is referenced, is not “common and confused.” The difference<br />

in signification between singular and general terms is <strong>the</strong>refore a matter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

presence or absence <strong>of</strong> confusion in imaging.<br />

Confusion in imaging just involves leaving out details <strong>of</strong> what is imaged. This<br />

omission is a cognitive limitation <strong>of</strong> sorts, but one which serves a purpose in that<br />

it allows <strong>the</strong> image to be variously applicable to differing objects — so long as<br />

<strong>the</strong> details it leaves out are <strong>the</strong> ones that constitute differences between <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Abelard takes for his example <strong>the</strong> image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lion, which may be so specified<br />

as to mark out <strong>the</strong> fact that it is limping, having been wounded by <strong>the</strong> spear <strong>of</strong><br />

Hercules; or it may lack such distinguishing marks [Abelard, 1919, p. 22 (18–22)].<br />

When lacking such marks, <strong>the</strong> image is more confused, but capable <strong>of</strong> conferring<br />

upon a term a more general range <strong>of</strong> application. When retaining such marks, <strong>the</strong><br />

image loses <strong>the</strong> confusion but also <strong>the</strong> general range. A general term, <strong>the</strong>n, works<br />

in this way: <strong>the</strong> understanding associated with it represents no member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

species with individuating detail, and so achieves representation <strong>of</strong> all members.<br />

Through this achievement it confers upon <strong>the</strong> term <strong>the</strong> ability to apply generally.<br />

Here, <strong>the</strong>n, is Abelard’s way <strong>of</strong> obviating reference to shared forms in accounting<br />

for <strong>the</strong> meaningfulness <strong>of</strong> general terms:<br />

Hence, when I hear “man” a certain figure (instar) arisesinmysoul<br />

which is related to single men in such a way as to be common to<br />

all and proper to none. But when I hear “Socrates” a certain form<br />

arises in my soul which expresses a likeness <strong>of</strong> a certain person. Hence,<br />

through this word “Socrates,” which presses upon <strong>the</strong> soul <strong>the</strong> proper<br />

form <strong>of</strong> one , a certain thing is indicated and determined; but<br />

through “man,” <strong>the</strong> understanding <strong>of</strong> which rests on a form common<br />

to all , <strong>the</strong> commonness itself stems from <strong>the</strong> confusion , so that we should not understand any one out <strong>of</strong> all<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m [Abelard, 1919, pp. 21 (32)–22 (2)]. 15<br />

“Form” and “figure” mean <strong>the</strong> same as “image” in this context. General terms<br />

are thus terms which arise from failure to image completely. This failure, however,<br />

is a matter <strong>of</strong> being partial as opposed to complete in <strong>the</strong>ir representation, and<br />

not a matter <strong>of</strong> being misleading as opposed to accurate. Nei<strong>the</strong>r “Socrates” nor<br />

“man” is a misleading term, but <strong>the</strong> latter is more partially representative than <strong>the</strong><br />

15 “Thing” in this citation translates res. For <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> this Latin term — so central for<br />

semantic <strong>the</strong>ory at this time — see [Jolivet, 1975, pp. 538–543], [Jolivet, 1982, p. 293, note 248]<br />

and [Kretzmann, 1982, p. 497].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!