22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Latin Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> to 1100 11<br />

In commenting On Interpretation, Boethius again turned to Porphyry, especially<br />

in <strong>the</strong> second, more advanced commentary [Boethius, 1880] (<strong>the</strong> first commentary<br />

[Boethius, 1877] was designed just as an aid for beginners to a literal understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> text). He says so himself [Boethius, 1877, 7:5-9], and it seems very likely<br />

that <strong>the</strong> very influential ideas on semantics and modality he puts forward were<br />

developed by Porphyry in his detailed commentary, now lost.<br />

At <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> On Interpretation, Aristotle says (to translate Boethius’s<br />

Latin version literally):<br />

The things <strong>the</strong>refore which are in <strong>the</strong> utterance (in voce) are <strong>the</strong> marks<br />

(notae) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> passions that are in <strong>the</strong> mind, and <strong>the</strong> things that are<br />

written <strong>of</strong> those that are in <strong>the</strong> utterance. And just as <strong>the</strong> letters are<br />

not <strong>the</strong> same for all, so <strong>the</strong> utterances are not <strong>the</strong> same; but what <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are primarily signs <strong>of</strong>, <strong>the</strong> passions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind, are <strong>the</strong> same for all,<br />

and <strong>the</strong> things too, <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong>se are likenesses, are <strong>the</strong> same. [16a1-8;<br />

Aristotle, 1965, 5:3-9; cf. Magee, 1989, 21-34]<br />

As <strong>the</strong> commentary as well as <strong>the</strong> translation shows, Boethius takes Aristotle to<br />

be presenting a semantics which is in many ways a mental language <strong>the</strong>ory. The<br />

‘passions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind’ are <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> this language which, unlike written and<br />

spoken languages, is common to all humans, and <strong>the</strong>se passions are in some way<br />

likenesses <strong>of</strong> objects in <strong>the</strong> world.<br />

To an extent, this is indeed Boethius’s approach. He speaks explicitly <strong>of</strong> mental<br />

discourse (oratio) [Boethius, 1880, 30], and he believes that <strong>the</strong> thoughts that<br />

are its simple terms are combined into complex thoughts that are true or false.<br />

There is, however, an important difference between Boethius’s thinking and a<br />

straightforward <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> this sort. When I utter ‘dog’ and you utter ‘dog’, we<br />

are speaking <strong>the</strong> same word in <strong>the</strong> sense that utterances are tokens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same<br />

type, in virtue <strong>of</strong> a physical resemblance between <strong>the</strong> sounds we produce, which<br />

a native speaker would judge to be close enough to take us as uttering <strong>the</strong> same<br />

word. What about my mental concept <strong>of</strong> dog and your one? For Boethius, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

can be called <strong>the</strong> same just because <strong>the</strong>y both [Boethius, 1880, 21:18-22] originate<br />

from <strong>the</strong> same type <strong>of</strong> animal. We begin from sensory contact with some object<br />

in <strong>the</strong> world, form a pre-conceptual image in our mind, on which <strong>the</strong> intellect<br />

works in order to have a thought <strong>of</strong> it. It seems, <strong>the</strong>refore, that in Boethian<br />

mental language, in so far as it is a language, <strong>the</strong> individual words (‘dog’, ‘cat’,<br />

‘human’) are not imposed on objects, as in a natural language, but derive from<br />

<strong>the</strong>m causally.<br />

When he comes to Chapter 9 <strong>of</strong> On Interpretation, Boethius has to give his<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> much debated passage on future contingents. Earlier (17a1-4) Aristotle<br />

had asserted <strong>the</strong> principal <strong>of</strong> bivalence: every proposition is ei<strong>the</strong>r true or<br />

false. But it seems that, if propositions about future events are true, or are false,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n no future events will be contingent. Suppose p states that a certain event E<br />

will happen tomorrow. If p is true, it seems that E must happen, and if p is false, it<br />

seems that E cannot happen, and so, whe<strong>the</strong>r p is true or false, E will not be con-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!