22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 125<br />

He supplies explicit definitions for both. The topical differentia is defined as<br />

“that thing (res) in whose relation to ano<strong>the</strong>r thing <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entailment<br />

resides” [Abelard, 1970, p. 263 (7–8)]. Since he speaks <strong>of</strong> a thing, not a word, we<br />

must understand <strong>the</strong> differentia in <strong>the</strong> above example as man, not “man” — or,<br />

more precisely, as man taken as a species, not “man” taken as a species. Abelard<br />

has presumably resolved to his satisfaction <strong>the</strong> metaphysical problems lurking in<br />

this use <strong>of</strong> general terms, so <strong>the</strong>se need not detain us. Considering man’s relation to<br />

animal prompts our taking man as a species, at which point <strong>the</strong> differentia is clear<br />

to view, and <strong>the</strong> maximal proposition on <strong>the</strong> way. It all starts with <strong>the</strong> relation<br />

<strong>of</strong> man to animal, and so it is in this relation that “<strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> entailment<br />

resides.”<br />

The account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> maximal proposition is more involved. Abelard defines it<br />

as “that proposition which, containing <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> many entailments, reveals a<br />

common method <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong> differentiae <strong>of</strong> those entailments possess —<br />

owing to <strong>the</strong>ir having <strong>the</strong> force <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same relation” [Abelard, 1970, p. 263 (12–<br />

14)]. 79 This is a densely packed formulation. The key feature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> above maximal<br />

proposition (“Whatever <strong>the</strong> species is predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genus is predicated too”)<br />

is its standing as a general expression <strong>of</strong> a whole series <strong>of</strong> entailments: “If it is a<br />

man it is an animal,” “If it is a pearl it is a stone,” “If it is a rose it is a flower,”<br />

“If it is red it is a colour,” and so on. These entailments have different terms<br />

(man and animal, pearl and stone, and so on), but are alike in that <strong>the</strong> terms are<br />

all related as species and genus. We can see each entailment as arising through<br />

<strong>the</strong> substitution <strong>of</strong> similarly related terms into <strong>the</strong> maximal proposition, which<br />

in this manner can be seen as “containing” <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> each. This is why <strong>the</strong><br />

maximal proposition plays a role in confirming each through a “common method<br />

<strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>.” This, as we have seen, starts by construing terms under <strong>the</strong> guise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

appropriate relation: man taken as species, pearl taken as species, rose taken as<br />

species, red taken as species, and so on. So construed <strong>the</strong>y become <strong>the</strong> differentiae,<br />

each <strong>of</strong> which gives rise to a method <strong>of</strong> proving <strong>the</strong> conditional from which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

arise — and it is <strong>the</strong> same method in each case. The maximal proposition reveals<br />

what this shared and common method is. 80<br />

This is <strong>the</strong> sense in which maximal propositions play for conditionals <strong>the</strong> role<br />

that syllogistic rules play for syllogisms: <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> reliably identifying which forms<br />

mark genuine entailments. The rule for Barbara (“If anything 〈A〉 is predicated<br />

<strong>of</strong> something 〈B〉 universally, and if something else 〈C〉 is subject to that subject<br />

〈B〉 universally, that subject 〈C〉 is also subject to <strong>the</strong> predicate 〈A〉 in <strong>the</strong> same<br />

way, that is universally” [Abelard, 1970, p. 237 (7–9)]) confirms as genuine entailments<br />

all <strong>of</strong> those syllogisms which arise from uniform substitution <strong>of</strong> terms in<br />

its open places (marked by “A”, “B”, and “C”.) The rule “Whatever <strong>the</strong> species<br />

is predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genus is predicated too” works in much <strong>the</strong> same way to con-<br />

79 On this passage see [Martin, 2004, pp. 174–175].<br />

80 Note that this account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essentials <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s topical <strong>the</strong>ory is based on texts from <strong>the</strong><br />

Dialectica. Certain aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> account change in his Super Topica glossae [Abelard, 1969b].<br />

For a summary <strong>of</strong> changes see [Green-Pedersen, 1977, pp. 135–137].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!