22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 199<br />

Variety 1 <strong>of</strong> Simple Supposition<br />

The simplest sort <strong>of</strong> simple supposition is given by <strong>the</strong> standard example:<br />

Man is a species<br />

As quoted above, Lambert describes this as a case in which a term has no relation<br />

at all to “<strong>the</strong> supposita”; that is, to <strong>the</strong> things that fall under <strong>the</strong> form that is<br />

signified. William similarly describes this kind <strong>of</strong> simple supposition as a case in<br />

which<br />

[A] a word is posited “without any connection with things”. [IL V.7<br />

(111)]<br />

In ei<strong>the</strong>r case this is pretty straightforward: <strong>the</strong> utterance is treated just as if <strong>the</strong><br />

term were a noun standing for <strong>the</strong> form that it signifies. 51<br />

Conceptualist alternatives are predictable: in this variety <strong>of</strong> simple supposition,<br />

<strong>the</strong> word stands for <strong>the</strong> concept it signifies, ei<strong>the</strong>r because that concept is <strong>the</strong> form,<br />

or because <strong>the</strong>re are no forms, but only concepts.<br />

Simple supposition occurs when a term supposits for an intention <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> soul and is not functioning significatively. For example, in ‘Man is<br />

a species’ <strong>the</strong> term ‘man’ supposits for an intention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, for it<br />

is that intention that is a species. [SL, 1.64 (190)]<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r varieties <strong>of</strong> simple supposition are more complex, and require additional<br />

discussion. Lambert describes <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r cases as ones in which <strong>the</strong>re is a relation<br />

to <strong>the</strong> supposita, “not determinately, but indeterminately”[PT 3g(ii)]. William<br />

divides <strong>the</strong>se into two types, and I’ll follow his classification. The examples that<br />

fall under <strong>the</strong>se two additional types were discussed by several authors.<br />

Variety 2 <strong>of</strong> Simple Supposition<br />

The second variety <strong>of</strong> simple supposition occurs when<br />

[a word is posited] for <strong>the</strong> significatum connected with things ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as it is actually preserved in every single thing, and is predicable <strong>of</strong> it<br />

[Sherwood IL V.7.2 (111)]<br />

The standard example which gives rise to this kind <strong>of</strong> simple supposition is:<br />

Man is <strong>the</strong> noblest <strong>of</strong> creatures<br />

51 In a very early anonymous writing (Cum sit nostra) <strong>the</strong> author maintains that in a proposition<br />

like ‘Man is a species’ <strong>the</strong>word‘man’ is not a common term at all, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a discrete<br />

name (like a proper name) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> species; this view is attributed to <strong>the</strong> grammarian Priscian.<br />

So it is not a common term used simply. This leaves unaddressed <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> what kind <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition it has, but it appears that it may have personal supposition here — since <strong>the</strong> word<br />

apparently supposits for what it names, not for what it signifies.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!