22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Assimilation <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian and Arabic <strong>Logic</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> Later Thirteenth Century 301<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>of</strong> Quaesitum IV deals with <strong>the</strong> mixed necessity and assertoric syllogisms.<br />

Averroes first states that <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> necessity propositions in Aristotle’s<br />

modal syllogistic are <strong>the</strong>mselves necessary and that such a term is one by virtue<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself (unus per se). What does this mean? A necessary term always stands for<br />

its subject. It is a name <strong>of</strong> a thing which is continuously actualised in <strong>the</strong> world,<br />

such as eternal individual beings, or natural species <strong>of</strong> substances and <strong>the</strong>ir essential<br />

properties. Averroes also states that <strong>the</strong>re are terms which are accidental.<br />

An accidental term does not always stand for <strong>the</strong> same subject, that is, <strong>the</strong> term<br />

sometimes stands for a certain subject and sometimes not.<br />

Given this, Averroes explains what constitutes a necessity proposition and what<br />

in general constitutes a assertoric proposition and a assertoric simpliciter proposition,<br />

which he thinks is <strong>the</strong> right type <strong>of</strong> assertoric premise in a mixed Aristotelian<br />

syllogism with necessity and assertoric premises. It is clear that if both terms in a<br />

proposition are necessary and an essential predicate is predicated <strong>of</strong> a (necessary)<br />

subject, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is necessary. According to Averroes, a proposition<br />

can be considered necessary if it consists <strong>of</strong> a necessary subject and a necessary<br />

predicate inhering in it ‘connexo ipsi subiecto’. This probably means that even if<br />

<strong>the</strong> property is not essential, but an inseparable accident (accidens inseparabile),<br />

such as <strong>the</strong> whiteness <strong>of</strong> swans, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is necessary.<br />

If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, both terms are accidental, and refer to properties which<br />

are not always actual, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is an assertoric proposition. Averroes<br />

is here interested in a special class <strong>of</strong> assertoric propositions, namely, in those<br />

which are assertoric simpliciter. If <strong>the</strong>y are true, <strong>the</strong>y are true independently<br />

<strong>of</strong> temporal restrictions whenever <strong>the</strong> subject is actual. His example <strong>of</strong> such an<br />

assertoric proposition is ‘Every walking being is moving’. He adds that if <strong>the</strong><br />

subject is walking it is necessarily moving. One could say that such propositions<br />

are conditionally necessary. 51<br />

The third suggestion discussed by Averroes is <strong>the</strong> combination <strong>of</strong> necessary and<br />

accidental terms. He first discusses <strong>the</strong> case in which <strong>the</strong> subject term is accidental<br />

and <strong>the</strong> predicate term is necessary. His example is ‘Every walking being is an<br />

animal’. This proposition can be understood in two ways: ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> subject term<br />

‘walking being’ is understood to stand for its supposita as walking, or it is taken<br />

to stand for <strong>the</strong>m as those which are walking. In <strong>the</strong> former case, <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

is assertoric, and in <strong>the</strong> latter case, it is necessary. Because <strong>the</strong> latter reading is<br />

indirect, it can be said that <strong>the</strong> proposition is a assertoric proposition per se and a<br />

necessity proposition per accidens. According to Averroes, in a mixed first figure<br />

syllogism with necessity and assertoric premises, <strong>the</strong> assertoric premise should be<br />

assertoric per se and necessary per accidens. One can ask, <strong>of</strong> course, why <strong>the</strong> minor<br />

premise is called an assertoric premise and <strong>the</strong> conclusion necessary. Both are<br />

assertoric per se and necessary per accidens. The second case with necessary and<br />

accidental terms is that <strong>the</strong> subject term is necessary and <strong>the</strong> predicate accidental.<br />

51 It was standard practice in Arabic logic after Avicenna to elaborate modal propositions<br />

with all kinds <strong>of</strong> restrictions placed on <strong>the</strong> terms involved. See [Street, 2004] and [Lagerlund,<br />

forthcoming b].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!